CINXE.COM
Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics | Britannica
<!doctype html> <html lang="en" class="topic-desktop ui-ie7 ui-ie"> <head prefix="og: https://ogp.me/ns# fb: https://ogp.me/ns/fb#"> <meta charset="utf-8"> <meta http-equiv="Content-Type" content="text/html; charset=UTF-8" /> <meta name="viewport" content="width=device-width, initial-scale=1.0" /> <link rel="dns-prefetch" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133"> <link rel="preconnect" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133"> <link rel="preload" as="script" href="https://www.googletagservices.com/tag/js/gpt.js" /> <link rel="icon" href="/favicon.png" /> <meta name="description" content="Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics: Although sensations (i.e., the conscious experiences that result from stimulation of the sense organs) are mental events, they seem to most people to be a source of information—fallible, perhaps, but in the main reliable—about a nonmental world, the world of material or physical objects, which constitutes the environment of the perceiver. Regarding that “external world,” many philosophers have attempted to answer the following related questions: Is there an external world? If there is, do the senses provide reliable information about it? If they do, do human beings know—or can they come to know—what the external world is like? If they" /> <meta name="keywords" content="metaphysics, encyclopedia, encyclopeadia, britannica, article" /> <link rel="canonical" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics" /> <title>Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics | Britannica</title> <!-- **** cafemedia top **** --> <script> !function(){"use strict";function e(e){const t=e.match(/((?=([a-z0-9._!#$%+^&*()[\]<>-]+))\2@[a-z0-9._-]+\.[a-z0-9._-]+)/gi);return t?t[0]:""}function t(t){return e(a(t.toLowerCase()))}function a(e){return e.replace(/\s/g,"")}async function n(e){const t={sha256Hash:"",sha1Hash:""};if(!("msCrypto"in window)&&"https:"===location.protocol&&"crypto"in window&&"TextEncoder"in window){const a=(new TextEncoder).encode(e),[n,c]=await Promise.all([s("SHA-256",a),s("SHA-1",a)]);t.sha256Hash=n,t.sha1Hash=c}return t}async function s(e,t){const a=await crypto.subtle.digest(e,t);return Array.from(new Uint8Array(a)).map(e=>("00"+e.toString(16)).slice(-2)).join("")}function c(e){let t=!0;return Object.keys(e).forEach(a=>{0===e[a].length&&(t=!1)}),t}function i(e,t,a){e.splice(t,1);const n="?"+e.join("&")+a.hash;history.replaceState(null,"",n)}var o={checkEmail:e,validateEmail:t,trimInput:a,hashEmail:n,hasHashes:c,removeEmailAndReplaceHistory:i,detectEmails:async function(){const e=new URL(window.location.href),a=Array.from(e.searchParams.entries()).map(e=>`=`);let s,o;const r=["adt_eih","sh_kit"];if(a.forEach((e,t)=>{const a=decodeURIComponent(e),[n,c]=a.split("=");if("adt_ei"===n&&(s={value:c,index:t,emsrc:"url"}),r.includes(n)){o={value:c,index:t,emsrc:"sh_kit"===n?"urlhck":"urlh"}}}),s)t(s.value)&&n(s.value).then(e=>{if(c(e)){const t={value:e,created:Date.now()};localStorage.setItem("adt_ei",JSON.stringify(t)),localStorage.setItem("adt_emsrc",s.emsrc)}});else if(o){const e={value:{sha256Hash:o.value,sha1Hash:""},created:Date.now()};localStorage.setItem("adt_ei",JSON.stringify(e)),localStorage.setItem("adt_emsrc",o.emsrc)}s&&i(a,s.index,e),o&&i(a,o.index,e)},cb:"adthrive"};const{detectEmails:r,cb:l}=o;r()}(); </script> <script type="text/javascript" data-type="Init Mendel"> window.$UI = {}; window.Constants = {"LICENSE_URL": "/bps/license","DEFAULT_TEST_VERSION": "A","DEFAULT_STATE": "XX","QUIZ_URL": "/quiz","SPOTLIGHT_BROWSE_URL": "/stories/spotlight","CONTENT_TYPE_TEXT": "text/plain;charset=UTF-8","TOPIC_FACTS_DATA_URL": "/facts","QUIZ_BROWSE_IMAGE_QUIZZES": "images","TOPIC_MEDIA_PATH": "/images-videos","USER_PROFILE_URL": "/user","DEBUG_URL": "/debug","ONE_GOOD_FACT_URL": "/one-good-fact","ERROR_404_URL": "/error404","PROCON_CITED_IN_THE_NEWS_URL": "/procon/ProCon-in-the-News","PROCON_URL": "/procon","TOPIC_PAGE_CONTENT_AJAX_URL": "/topic-content/page","INFINITE_SCROLL_PREFIX_URL": "/scroll","TOPIC_TOP_QUESTION_BROWSE_URL": "/questions","CC_USD": "USD","domain": "britannica.com","PROCON_EDITOR_ID": "12941390","SURVEY_URL": "/survey","CATEGORY_BROWSE_URL": "/browse","STORY_BROWSE_URL": "/stories","COUNTRY_US": "US","OPEN_MEDIA_OVERLAY_PARAMETER": "/media","NEWSLETTER_SUBSCRIPTION_URL": "/newsletter-subscription","MAINTENANCE_ERROR_URL": "https://maintenance.eb.com","IMARS_EDITOR_ID": "12365882","PROFILE_EB_EDITOR_URL": "/editor","WEB_INF_RESOURCES_PATH": "WEB-INF/resources","AI_ABOUT_PAGE_URL": "/about-britannica-ai","TOPIC_ADDITIONAL_INFO_PATH": "/additional-info","SUDOKU_GAME_URL": "/games/sudoku","CC_INR": "INR","ARTICLE_PRINT_URL": "/print/article","FIRST_EDITION_URL": "/subscriber/firstedition","WW1_PORTAL_URL": "/discover/World-War-I","MENDEL_COOKIE": "__mendel","topicUrlClasses": "[topic, animal, art, biography, event, place, plant, science, sports, technology, procon, money]","DEMYSTIFIED_BROWSE_URL": "/stories/demystified","LIST_BROWSE_URL": "/list/browse","PROFILE_EXPERT_URL": "/contributor","ASSEMBLY_IMAGE_URL": "/image/assembly","DAY_IN_HISTORY_URL": "/on-this-day","DEFAULT_CURRENCY": "USD","CONTENT_TYPE_XML": "text/xml;charset=UTF-8","PORTAL_FINANCE_BROWSE_URL_PREFIX": "/money/browse","MONEY_IMARS_CATEGORY": "13000","AJAX_PREFIX_URL": "/ajax","TOPIC_BROWSE_URL": "/topic-browse","MARKETING_CONTENT": "/marketing-content","ENV_RUNTIME": "runtime","GALLERY_URL": "/gallery","topicUrlClassesList": "topic|animal|art|biography|event|place|plant|science|sports|technology|procon","CONTENT_TYPE_HTML": "text/html;charset=UTF-8","ENV_LOCAL": "override","MEDIA_OVERLAY_URL": "/media-overlay","CHATBOT_PAGE_URL": "/chatbot","NEWSLETTER_PAGE_URL": "/newsletters","ENV_DEV": "development","MEDIA_URL": "/media","TOPIC_TOP_QUESTION_URL": "/question","PORTAL_FINANCE_URL_PREFIX": "/money","PODCASTS_URL": "/podcasts","STAND_ALONE_VIDEO_URL": "/video","MORE_ON_THIS_DAY_URL": "/more-on-this-day","TOPIC_QUOTES_URL": "/quotes","SEARCH_PAGE_URL": "/search","PROCON_CLASS": "PROCON","KUSTOM_MENDEL_APPLICATION_ID": "1","TOPIC_CONTENT_AJAX_URL": "/topic-content/topic","ENV_BRANCH": "branch","ERROR_URL": "/error","MAIN_VERSION": "mainVersion","TOPIC_COLLECTION_URL": "/summary","LOGINBOX_URL": "/auth/loginbox","PROCON_DEBATE_TOPICS_URL": "/procon/Debate-Topics","ONE_GOOD_FACT_BROWSE_URL": "/one-good-fact/all-good-facts","QUIZ_BROWSE_URL": "/quiz/browse","BIO_BROWSE_URL": "/browse/biographies","LIST_URL": "/list","TIGHTROPE_QUIZ_URL": "/quiz/tightrope","ALPHA_BROWSE_URL": "/sitemap","CONTENT_TYPE_JSON": "application/json","DICTIONARY_URL": "/dictionary","COBRAND_IMAGE_URL": "/image/cobrand","PROCON_IN_THE_NEWS_URL": "/procon/pro-and-con-issues-in-the-news","PROCON_BROWSE_URL": "/procon","QUIZ_BROWSE_VOCAB_QUIZZES": "vocabulary-quizzes","SUBMISSION_URL": "/submission","EB_LOG_OUT": "/auth2/logout","ENV_PRODUCTION": "production","EXPLORE_PORTAL_URL": "/explore","TOPIC_AJAX_URL": "/ajax/topic","TOPIC_SUMMARY_BROWSE_URL": "/summaries","WTFACT_BROWSE_URL": "/stories/wtfact","VIDEO_CHANNEL_URL": "/videos","GALLERY_BROWSE_URL": "/gallery/browse","CACHE_URL": "/cache","PROCON_ABOUT_URL": "/procon/About-ProCon","COMPANION_BROWSE_URL": "/stories/companion","MEDIA_FOLDER": "/eb-media","SHOW_ALL_CONTRIBUTORS": "/additional-info#contributors","BRITANNICA_EDITORS_ID": "4419","ENV_CACHE_DISABLED": "mendelCache","CALCULATORS_BROWSE_URL": "/calculators","STORY_URL": "/story","DEFAULT_COUNTRY": "US","NAVBAR_URL": "/ajax/navbar","EB_LOGIN_URL": "/auth/eb-login","NEW_ARTICLES_URL": "/new-articles",}; window.CDN = "https://cdn.britannica.com"; window.CAM_SETTINGS_URL = "https://cam.britannica.com/settings"; window.CAM_LOGIN_URL = "https://cam.britannica.com/login"; window.CAM_SIGN_UP_URL = "https://cam.britannica.com/registration" window.Mendel = { "config" : { "domain": "britannica.com", "page": "Topic", "videoPlayerId": "UyMCoK2v", "sharedUrl": "https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics", "amuselabsUrl": "https://cdn3.amuselabs.com", "resourcesPrefixUrl": "https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/[url]?v=3.133.9", "date": 20250217, "userInfo": { "type": "ANONYMOUS" ,"currency": "AUUS" ,"country": "SG" ,"state": "XX" ,"timezone": "Asia/Singapore" ,"bcomId": "-3241352347404838190" ,"hasAds": true ,"testVersion": "D" ,"adsTestVersion": "C" ,"consumerId": "" ,"instId": "" ,"consumerUserName": "" ,"instUserName": "" ,"cognito": null }, "tvs":{ "r":[25,25,25,25], "a": [25,25,45,5]}, "isLoggedInAsUser": false, "isPhone": false, "isDesktop": true, "logoutUrl": "/auth2/logout", "selfServiceUrl": "https://myaccount.britannica.com", "cdnUrl": "https://cdn.britannica.com", "chatbotApi": "https://www.britannica.com/chat-api", "fetchOffset": 800, "mendelCookieName": "__mendel", "mendelCookie": {"surveyShown":false,"visitedTopicId":377923,"currentDate":20250217}, "autocompleteToSearchPage": false,"topicUrl": "https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics", "freeTopicReason": "NO_REFERRER", "topicId": 377923, "template": "DESKTOP", "type": "CORE", "hasToc": true, "chatbotApi": "https://www.britannica.com/chat-api", "showPreview": false, }, "GA": {"leg":"D","adLeg":"C","userType":"ANONYMOUS","pageType":"Topic","articleTemplateType":"PAGINATED","gisted":false,"pageNumber":2,"hasSummarizeButton":false,"hasAskButton":true} }; </script> <meta property="fb:app_id" content="1887621861548296"/ <meta name="twitter:card" content="summary_large_image" /> <meta name="twitter:site" content="@britannica" /> <meta name="twitter:image" content="https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-050-7C5547FE/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg" /> <meta name="twitter:description" content="Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics: Although sensations (i.e., the conscious experiences that result from stimulation of the sense organs) are mental events, they seem to most people to be a source of information—fallible, perhaps, but in the main reliable—about a nonmental world, the world of material or physical objects, which constitutes the environment of the perceiver. Regarding that “external world,” many philosophers have attempted to answer the following related questions: Is there an external world? If there is, do the senses provide reliable information about it? If they do, do human beings know—or can they come to know—what the external world is like? If they"/> <meta property="og:type" content="ARTICLE"/> <meta property="og:title" content="Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics | Britannica"/> <meta property="og:description" content="Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics: Although sensations (i.e., the conscious experiences that result from stimulation of the sense organs) are mental events, they seem to most people to be a source of information—fallible, perhaps, but in the main reliable—about a nonmental world, the world of material or physical objects, which constitutes the environment of the perceiver. Regarding that “external world,” many philosophers have attempted to answer the following related questions: Is there an external world? If there is, do the senses provide reliable information about it? If they do, do human beings know—or can they come to know—what the external world is like? If they"/> <meta property="og:site_name" content="Encyclopedia Britannica" /> <meta property="og:url" content="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics"/> <meta property="og:image" content="https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-050-7C5547FE/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg" /> <meta property="og:image:type" content="image/jpeg" /> <script type="text/javascript" data-type="init opengraph"> Mendel.openGraph = {"type":"ARTICLE","title":"Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics","description":"Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics: Although sensations (i.e., the conscious experiences that result from stimulation of the sense organs) are mental events, they seem to most people to be a source of information—fallible, perhaps, but in the main reliable—about a nonmental world, the world of material or physical objects, which constitutes the environment of the perceiver. Regarding that “external world,” many philosophers have attempted to answer the following related questions: Is there an external world? If there is, do the senses provide reliable information about it? If they do, do human beings know—or can they come to know—what the external world is like? If they","imageUrl":"https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-050-7C5547FE/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg","imageType":"image/jpeg","pageUrl":"https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics"}</script> <link rel="preconnect" href="https://fonts.googleapis.com/"> <link rel="dns-prefetch" href="https://fonts.googleapis.com/" > <link rel="stylesheet" href="https://fonts.googleapis.com/icon?family=Material+Icons"> <link href="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/dist/vendor-bundle.css?v=3.133.9" rel="stylesheet" /> <link href="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/dist/mendel-css.css?v=3.133.9" rel="stylesheet" /> <link href="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/dist/topic-page.css?v=3.133.9" rel="stylesheet" /> <script type="text/javascript"> if (self !== top) { top.location = self.location; } </script> <script src="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/js/at.js?v=3.133.9" async ></script> <script> dataLayer = []; </script> <script type="text/javascript">(function(w,d,s,l,i){w[l]=w[l]||[];w[l].push({'gtm.start': new Date().getTime(),event:'gtm.js'});var f=d.getElementsByTagName(s)[0], j=d.createElement(s),dl=l!='dataLayer'?'&l='+l:'';j.async=true;j.src= '//www.googletagmanager.com/gtm.js?id='+i+dl;f.parentNode.insertBefore(j,f); })(window,document,'script','dataLayer','GTM-5W6NC8'); </script> <script type="application/ld+json"> {"headline":"Metaphysics | Definition, Problems, Theories, History, & Criticism","image":{"url":"https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-050-7C5547FE/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg","@type":"ImageObject"},"author":[{"name":"Peter van Inwagen","url":"https://www.britannica.com/contributor/Peter-van-Inwagen/6110","@type":"Person"},{"name":"A.C. Grayling","url":"https://www.britannica.com/contributor/AC-Grayling/1140","@type":"Person"}],"keywords":"metaphysics","wordcount":28971,"url":"https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics","datePublished":"1999-07-26T00:00:00Z","description":"Metaphysics, branch of philosophy whose topics in antiquity and the Middle Ages were the first causes of things and the nature of being. Later, many other topics came to be included under the heading ‘metaphysics.’ The set of problems that now make up the subject matter of metaphysics is extremely diverse.","publisher":{"name":"Encyclopedia Britannica","@type":"Organization","logo":{"url":"https://corporate.britannica.com/wp-content/themes/eb-corporate/_img/logo.png","@type":"ImageObject"}},"@context":"https://schema.org","@type":"article"} </script> </head> <body data-leg="D" class="new-topic topic-desktop first-page-false user-ANONYMOUS user-ads md-desktop leg-d b-ie"> <!-- **** cafemedia **** --> <script>Mendel.config.adProvider='cafemedia';</script> <script data-no-optimize="1" data-cfasync="false"> (function(w, d) { w.adthrive = w.adthrive || {}; w.adthrive.cmd = w. adthrive.cmd || []; w.adthrive.plugin = 'adthrive-ads-manual'; w.adthrive.host = 'ads.adthrive.com';var s = d.createElement('script'); s.async = true; s.referrerpolicy='no-referrer-when-downgrade'; s.src = 'https://' + w.adthrive.host + '/sites/61575e5c934c481d714b3ca9/ads.min.js?referrer=' + w.encodeURIComponent(w.location.href) + '&cb=' + (Math.floor(Math.random() * 100) + 1); var n = d.getElementsByTagName('script')[0]; n.parentNode.insertBefore(s, n); })(window, document); </script> <div class="ie-warning d-flex align-items-center align-self-center justify-content-center site-alert bg-orange"> <div> You are using an <strong>outdated</strong> browser. Please <a class="text-white text-underscore" href="https://browsehappy.com/">upgrade your browser</a> to improve your experience and security. </div> </div> <script id="json-navbar-info" type="application/json"> {"topSectionLinks":[{"title":"Ask the Chatbot","url":"/chatbot","navbarId":"CHATBOT"},{"title":"Games & Quizzes","url":"/quiz/browse","navbarId":"QUIZZES"},{"title":"History & Society","url":"/History-Society","selected":true,"navbarId":"HISTORY"},{"title":"Science & Tech","url":"/Science-Tech","navbarId":"SCIENCE"},{"title":"Biographies","url":"/Biographies","navbarId":"BIOS"},{"title":"Animals & Nature","url":"/Animals-Nature","navbarId":"ANIMALS"},{"title":"Geography & Travel","url":"/Geography-Travel","navbarId":"GEOGRAPHY"},{"title":"Arts & Culture","url":"/Arts-Culture","navbarId":"ART"},{"title":"ProCon","url":"/procon","navbarId":"PROCON"},{"title":"Money","url":"/money","navbarId":"MONEY"},{"title":"Videos","url":"/videos","navbarId":"VIDEOS"}],"selectedSuperCategory":{"id":5,"title":"History & Society","url":"History-Society","description":"Explore history and society; accidents and disasters; the age of revolutions; the ancient world; historic dynasties; global exploration; the middle ages; the modern world; prehistory; US history; world history; wars and battles; sociology; religion and philosophy; humanities; ethics; anthropology; festivals and holidays; human rights; human migration; international relations; politics, law, and government","keywords":"accidents and disasters; the age of revolutions; the ancient world; historic dynasties; global exploration; the middle ages; the modern world; prehistory; US history; world history; wars and battles; sociology; religion and philosophy; humanities; ethics; anthropology; festivals and holidays; human rights; human migration; international relations; politics, law, and government","classId":"HISTORY","sortOrder":1},"selectedNavbarLink":{"title":"History & Society","url":"/History-Society","selected":true,"navbarId":"HISTORY"}} </script> <script id="json-hamburger-menu" type="application/json"> {"britannicaMenu1":[{"title":"Home","url":"/"},{"title":"History & Society","url":"/History-Society"},{"title":"Science & Tech","url":"/Science-Tech"},{"title":"Biographies","url":"/Biographies"},{"title":"Animals & Nature","url":"/Animals-Nature"},{"title":"Geography & Travel","url":"/Geography-Travel"},{"title":"Arts & Culture","url":"/Arts-Culture"},{"title":"ProCon","url":"/procon"},{"title":"Money","url":"/money"}],"britannicaMenu2":[{"title":"Games & Quizzes","url":"/quiz/browse"},{"title":"Videos","url":"/videos"},{"title":"On This Day","url":"/on-this-day"},{"title":"One Good Fact","url":"/one-good-fact"},{"title":"Dictionary","url":"/dictionary"},{"title":"New Articles","url":"/new-articles"}],"browseByCategory":[{"title":{"id":5,"title":"History & Society","url":"/History-Society"},"links":[{"title":"Lifestyles & Social Issues","url":"/browse/Lifestyles-Social-Issues"},{"title":"Philosophy & Religion","url":"/browse/Philosophy-Religion"},{"title":"Politics, Law & Government","url":"/browse/Politics-Law-Government"},{"title":"World History","url":"/browse/World-History"}]},{"title":{"id":6,"title":"Science & Tech","url":"/Science-Tech"},"links":[{"title":"Health & Medicine","url":"/browse/Health-Medicine"},{"title":"Science","url":"/browse/Science"},{"title":"Technology","url":"/browse/Technology"}]},{"title":{"id":3,"title":"Biographies","url":"/Biographies"},"links":[{"title":"Browse Biographies","url":"/browse/biographies"}]},{"title":{"id":1,"title":"Animals & Nature","url":"/Animals-Nature"},"links":[{"title":"Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates","url":"/browse/Birds-Reptiles-Vertebrates"},{"title":"Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates","url":"/browse/Bugs-Mollusks-Invertebrates"},{"title":"Environment","url":"/browse/Environment"},{"title":"Fossils & Geologic Time","url":"/browse/Fossil-Geologic-Time"},{"title":"Mammals","url":"/browse/Mammals"},{"title":"Plants","url":"/browse/Plants"}]},{"title":{"id":4,"title":"Geography & Travel","url":"/Geography-Travel"},"links":[{"title":"Geography & Travel","url":"/browse/Geography-Travel"}]},{"title":{"id":2,"title":"Arts & Culture","url":"/Arts-Culture"},"links":[{"title":"Entertainment & Pop Culture","url":"/browse/Entertainment-Pop-Culture"},{"title":"Literature","url":"/browse/Literature"},{"title":"Sports & Recreation","url":"/browse/Sports-Recreation"},{"title":"Visual Arts","url":"/browse/Visual-Arts"}]}],"browseByFeature":[{"title":"Companions","url":"/stories/companion"},{"title":"Demystified","url":"/stories/demystified"},{"title":"Image Galleries","url":"/gallery/browse"},{"title":"Lists","url":"/list/browse"},{"title":"Podcasts","url":"/podcasts"},{"title":"Spotlight","url":"/stories/spotlight"},{"title":"Summaries","url":"/summary"},{"title":"The Forum","url":"/stories/the-forum"},{"title":"Top Questions","url":"/question"},{"title":"#WTFact","url":"/stories/wtfact"}],"moreFromBritannica":[{"title":"Britannica Kids","url":"https://kids.britannica.com/","newTab":true}],"menuType":"DEFAULT"} </script> <header id="header" class="bg-navy-dark"> <div class="global-nav-top-bar"> <div class="grid gx-0 h-100 justify-content-between align-items-center container-lg mx-auto p-0 position-relative"> <div class="d-flex align-items-center"> <button class="d-flex align-items-center justify-self-start js-toggle js-toggle-hamburger btn btn-link link-white btn-sm rounded-0 p-10"> <div class="hamburger-tooltip"> <em class="material-icons d-inline-block font-24" id="nav-toggle" data-icon="menu"></em> </div> <em class="material-icons d-inline-block font-24 global-nav-search-icon" id="nav-search-icon" data-icon="search" ></em> </button> <a href="/" class="d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center ml-10"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel/eb-logo/MendelNewThistleLogo.png" alt="Encyclopedia Britannica" class="global-nav-logo global-nav-logo-left" /> </a> <div class="global-nav-top-search-bar global-nav-top-search-container global-nav-search-container" id="global-nav-top-search-bar"> <form method="get" action="/search" id="global-nav-search" class="md-search-form m-0 global-nav-search-bar-small"> <div class="search-box position-relative col-100"> <label class="sr-only" for="global-nav-search-query">Search Britannica</label> <input name="query" id="global-nav-search-query" placeholder="Search Britannica..." class="form-control form-control-lg rounded-lg font-16 search-query pl-20 pr-70 shadow-sm" maxlength="200" autocomplete="off" aria-label="Search Britannica" /> <button class="search-reset-btn btn btn-link px-10 position-absolute top-0 h-100 d-none" type="reset"> <em class="material-icons" data-icon="close"></em> </button> <button class="search-submit btn btn-link text-blue px-10 position-absolute top-0 right-0 h-100" type="submit" disabled> <span class="sr-only">Click here to search</span> <em class="material-icons search-icon" data-icon="search"></em> </button> </div> </form> </div> </div> <a href="/" class="d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel/eb-logo/MendelNewThistleLogo.png" alt="Encyclopedia Britannica" class="global-nav-center global-nav-logo non-homepage-logo" /> </a> <form method="get" action="/search" id="global-nav-search" class="md-search-form m-0 global-nav-search-bar-small global-nav-center search global-nav-center-search-container"> <div class="search-box position-relative col-100"> <label class="sr-only" for="global-nav-search-query">Search Britannica</label> <input name="query" id="global-nav-search-query" placeholder="Search Britannica..." class="form-control form-control-lg rounded-lg font-16 search-query pl-20 pr-70 shadow-sm" maxlength="200" autocomplete="off" aria-label="Search Britannica" /> <button class="search-reset-btn btn btn-link px-10 position-absolute top-0 h-100 d-none" type="reset"> <em class="material-icons" data-icon="close"></em> </button> <button class="search-submit btn btn-link text-blue px-10 position-absolute top-0 right-0 h-100" type="submit" disabled> <span class="sr-only">Click here to search</span> <em class="material-icons search-icon" data-icon="search"></em> </button> </div> </form> <div class="col-35 col-sm-auto text-right order-3 mr-lg-15 align-items-center d-flex justify-content-end"> <div class="d-none d-md-inline-block"> <SPAN class="marketing-HEADER_SUBSCRIPTION_DESKTOP2 marketing-content" data-marketing-id="HEADER_SUBSCRIPTION_DESKTOP2"><a href="https://premium.britannica.com/premium-membership/?utm_source=premium&utm_medium=global-nav&utm_campaign=evergreen-cap" class="subscribe-link btn btn-sm btn-orange py-5 mr-10" target="_blank" rel="noopener"> SUBSCRIBE </a></SPAN></div> <div class="d-inline-block d-md-none mr-5 mr-sm-10"> <SPAN class="marketing-HEADER_SUBSCRIPTION_MOBILE marketing-content" data-marketing-id="HEADER_SUBSCRIPTION_MOBILE"><a href="https://premium.britannica.com/premium-membership/?utm_source=premium&utm_medium=global-nav-mobile&utm_campaign=evergreen" class="subscribe-link btn btn-xs btn-orange p-5" target="_blank" rel="noopener"> SUBSCRIBE </a></SPAN></div> <button class="js-toggle-user-dropdown js-toggle btn btn-sm btn-link link-white rounded-0 px-md-15 pl-5 pr-5"> <span class="d-none d-md-inline-block mr-5">Login</span> <em class="material-icons d-inline-block d-md-none font-16 font-sm-20" data-icon="account_circle"></em> <div class="d-none dropdown-menu-subscription-link">https://premium.britannica.com/premium-membership/?utm_source=premium&utm_medium=nav-login-box&utm_campaign=evergreen</div> <em class="material-icons inactive-icon d-inline-block font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_down"></em> <em class="material-icons active-icon d-inline-block font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_up"></em> </button> </div> </div> </div> <div class="d-none hamburger-menu-subscription-link"><DIV class="marketing-HAMBURGER_MENU_CTA marketing-content" data-marketing-id="HAMBURGER_MENU_CTA"><a href="https://premium.britannica.com/premium-membership/?utm_source=premium&utm_medium=hamburger-menu&utm_campaign=evergreen" class="subscribe-link btn btn-sm btn-orange py-5" target="_blank"> SUBSCRIBE </a></DIV></div> <div id="global-nav-react"> <div class="d-none"> <ul> <li><a href="/">Home</a></li> <li><a href="/History-Society">History & Society</a></li> <li><a href="/Science-Tech">Science & Tech</a></li> <li><a href="/Biographies">Biographies</a></li> <li><a href="/Animals-Nature">Animals & Nature</a></li> <li><a href="/Geography-Travel">Geography & Travel</a></li> <li><a href="/Arts-Culture">Arts & Culture</a></li> <li><a href="/procon">ProCon</a></li> <li><a href="/money">Money</a></li> </ul> <ul> <li><a href="/quiz/browse">Games & Quizzes</a></li> <li><a href="/videos">Videos</a></li> <li><a href="/on-this-day">On This Day</a></li> <li><a href="/one-good-fact">One Good Fact</a></li> <li><a href="/dictionary">Dictionary</a></li> <li><a href="/new-articles">New Articles</a></li> </ul> <a href="/History-Society">History & Society</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/Lifestyles-Social-Issues">Lifestyles & Social Issues</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Philosophy-Religion">Philosophy & Religion</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Politics-Law-Government">Politics, Law & Government</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/World-History">World History</a></li> </ul> <a href="/Science-Tech">Science & Tech</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/Health-Medicine">Health & Medicine</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Science">Science</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Technology">Technology</a></li> </ul> <a href="/Biographies">Biographies</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/biographies">Browse Biographies</a></li> </ul> <a href="/Animals-Nature">Animals & Nature</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/Birds-Reptiles-Vertebrates">Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Bugs-Mollusks-Invertebrates">Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Environment">Environment</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Fossil-Geologic-Time">Fossils & Geologic Time</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Mammals">Mammals</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Plants">Plants</a></li> </ul> <a href="/Geography-Travel">Geography & Travel</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/Geography-Travel">Geography & Travel</a></li> </ul> <a href="/Arts-Culture">Arts & Culture</a> <ul> <li><a href="/browse/Entertainment-Pop-Culture">Entertainment & Pop Culture</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Literature">Literature</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Sports-Recreation">Sports & Recreation</a></li> <li><a href="/browse/Visual-Arts">Visual Arts</a></li> </ul> <ul> <li><a href="/stories/companion">Companions</a></li> <li><a href="/stories/demystified">Demystified</a></li> <li><a href="/gallery/browse">Image Galleries</a></li> <li><a href="/list/browse">Lists</a></li> <li><a href="/podcasts">Podcasts</a></li> <li><a href="/stories/spotlight">Spotlight</a></li> <li><a href="/summary">Summaries</a></li> <li><a href="/stories/the-forum">The Forum</a></li> <li><a href="/question">Top Questions</a></li> <li><a href="/stories/wtfact">#WTFact</a></li> </ul> <ul> <li><a href="https://kids.britannica.com/">Britannica Kids</a></li> </ul> </div> </div> </header> <div class="bg-navy-dark"> <div class="container-lg p-0 d-flex justify-content-center global-nav-categories-bar overflow-hidden"> <div class="slider js-slider position-relative d-inline-flex align-items-center mw-100 global-nav-slider category-snap-slider"> <div class="slider-container js-slider-container overflow-hidden d-flex font-14 overflow-hidden text-nowrap mx-5"> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-CHATBOT " href="/chatbot">Ask the Chatbot</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-QUIZZES " href="/quiz/browse">Games & Quizzes</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-HISTORY selected selected" href="/History-Society">History & Society</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-SCIENCE " href="/Science-Tech">Science & Tech</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-BIOS " href="/Biographies">Biographies</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-ANIMALS " href="/Animals-Nature">Animals & Nature</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-GEOGRAPHY " href="/Geography-Travel">Geography & Travel</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-ART " href="/Arts-Culture">Arts & Culture</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-PROCON " href="/procon">ProCon</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-MONEY " href="/money">Money</a> <a class="nav-bar-category mx-5 category-link-VIDEOS " href="/videos">Videos</a> </div> <button disabled class="prev-button js-prev-button position-absolute btn btn-circle shadow btn-blue " aria-label="Previous"> <span class="material-icons md-24" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_left"></span> </button> <button disabled class="next-button js-next-button position-absolute btn btn-circle shadow btn-blue " aria-label="Next"> <span class="material-icons md-24" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></span> </button> </div> </div> </div> <main> <div class="md-page-wrapper"> <div id="content" class="md-content"> <div class="md-article-container template-desktop infinite-pagination"> <div class="infinite-scroll-container article last"> <script> Object.assign( window.Mendel.config, { "infiniteScrollList": [{"p":4,"t":377923},{"p":13,"t":190219},{"p":17,"t":383556},{"p":10,"t":754957},{"p":10,"t":139301},{"p":29,"t":557348},{"p":1,"t":218436},{"p":1,"t":452945},{"p":1,"t":159526},{"p":2,"t":1519127}], "sequence": 2, "topics": {} }); </script> <article class="article-content container-lg qa-content px-0 pt-0 pb-40 py-lg-20 content md-expanded" data-topic-id="377923"> <div class="grid gx-0"> <div class="col-auto"> <div class="topic-left-rail md-article-drawer position-relative d-flex border-right-sm border-left-sm open"> <div class="drawer d-flex flex-column open"> <div class="left-rail-section-content"> <div class="topic-left-rail-header text-truncate bg-gray-50 position-relative text-right d-flex align-items-center"> <div class="tlr-title px-20 py-15 text-left"> <em class="material-icons text-gray-400 d-lg-none" data-icon="toc"></em> <a class="font-serif font-weight-bold text-black link-blue" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics">metaphysics</a> </div> <button aria-label="Close" class="js-sections-close-button btn-link btn-sm btn d-lg-none position-absolute top-0 p-10 right-0" > <em class="material-icons font-26" data-icon="close"></em> </button> </div> <div class="section-content pl-10 pr-20 pl-sm-50 pr-sm-60 pl-lg-5 pr-lg-10 pt-10 pt-lg-0 bg-gray-50 clear-catfish-ad"> <div class="toc mb-20"> <div class="font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mx-15 mb-15 mt-20"> Table of Contents </div> <ul class="list-unstyled my-0" data-level="h1"><li data-target="#ref1"><div class="pl-25"><a class="link-gray-900 w-100" href="/topic/metaphysics">Introduction</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"></div></li><li data-target="#ref344380"><div class="d-flex align-items-center"><div class="ml-25"></div><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics#ref344380">Nature and scope of metaphysics</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"></div></li><li data-target="#ref15809"><div class="d-flex align-items-center"><button class="h1-link-drawer-button btn btn-xs btn-circle d-flex rounded" type="button" aria-label="Toggle Heading"><em class="material-icons font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></em></button><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics">Problems in metaphysics</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344383"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344383">The reality of the external world</a><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344384"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344384">The problem in early modern philosophy</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344385"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344385">Berkeleyan idealism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344386"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344386">The problem in 20th-century and later philosophy</a></li></ul></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344387"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344387">Mind and body</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344388"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344388">Existence</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344389"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344389">Universals and particulars</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344390"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344390">Causation</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344391"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344391">Substance</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344392"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344392">Identity</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344393"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344393">Persistence through time</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344394"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344394">Modality</a></li></ul></div></li><li data-target="#ref15839"><div class="d-flex align-items-center"><button class="h1-link-drawer-button btn btn-xs btn-circle d-flex rounded" type="button" aria-label="Toggle Heading"><em class="material-icons font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></em></button><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Types-of-metaphysical-theory">Types of metaphysical theory</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15840"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Types-of-metaphysical-theory#ref15840">Platonism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15841"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Types-of-metaphysical-theory#ref15841">Aristotelianism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15842"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Types-of-metaphysical-theory#ref15842">Thomism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15843"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism">Cartesianism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344403"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344403">Kantianism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15844"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref15844">Idealism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref15845"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref15845">Materialism</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344404"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344404">Naturalism</a></li></ul></div></li><li data-target="#ref344369"><div class="d-flex align-items-center"><button class="h1-link-drawer-button btn btn-xs btn-circle d-flex rounded" type="button" aria-label="Toggle Heading"><em class="material-icons font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></em></button><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344369">Contemporary metaphysics</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344370"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344370">Analytic metaphysics in the 20th century</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344371"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344371">Continental metaphysics in the 20th century</a></li></ul></div></li><li data-target="#ref344372"><div class="d-flex align-items-center"><button class="h1-link-drawer-button btn btn-xs btn-circle d-flex rounded" type="button" aria-label="Toggle Heading"><em class="material-icons font-18" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></em></button><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344372">Criticisms of metaphysics</a></div><div class="ml-40 toc-drawer sub-toc-drawer"><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344373"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344373">The epistemology of metaphysics</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h2"><li data-target="#ref344374"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344374">Specific criticisms</a><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344375"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344375">Hume</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344376"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344376">Kant</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344377"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344377">The logical positivists</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344378"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344378">Moore and Wittgenstein</a></li></ul><ul class="list-unstyled" data-level="h3"><li data-target="#ref344379"><a class="w-100 link-gray-900" href="/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref344379">Postmodern and other Continental critiques</a></li></ul></li></ul></div></li></ul> <a class="toc-extra-link link-gray-900" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/additional-info">References & Edit History</a> <a class="toc-extra-link link-gray-900" href="/facts/metaphysics">Related Topics</a> </div> <div class="tlr-media-slider pb-10 mb-30"> <a class="section-header link-gray-900 font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mb-10 mx-10" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/images-videos">Images</a> <div class="slider js-slider position-relative d-inline-flex align-items-center mw-100 "> <div class="slider-container js-slider-container overflow-hidden d-flex overflow-hidden text-nowrap ml-15"> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-050-7C5547FE/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/95965" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/84/87984-004-5ADE9ACA/Detail-Roman-copy-portrait-bust-Aristotle-Greek.jpg" alt="Aristotle" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-050-439A37F8/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/238240" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-004-F05D85FB/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg" alt="René Descartes" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-050-572BA52D/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/68890" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-004-F44C2DE8/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg" alt="George Berkeley" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-050-D9456DAA/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/13074" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-004-458DEF80/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg" alt="G.E. Moore" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/11500" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg" alt="Martin Heidegger" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-050-6422D72B/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/200662" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-004-A064E74D/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg" alt="Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-050-404073CE/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/128314" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-004-A3DFC9A4/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg" alt="David Hume" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-050-79127006/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/110184" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-004-9E5426BE/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg" alt="Immanuel Kant" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-050-F6C9719C/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/122142" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-004-964F40A4/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg" alt="Benedict de Spinoza" height="50" /> </a> <a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/99991" class="media-overlay-link d-inline-block mr-5"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg" alt="David Kellogg Lewis" height="50" /> </a> </div> <button disabled class="prev-button js-prev-button position-absolute btn btn-circle shadow btn-blue " aria-label="Previous"> <span class="material-icons md-24" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_left"></span> </button> <button disabled class="next-button js-next-button position-absolute btn btn-circle shadow btn-blue " aria-label="Next"> <span class="material-icons md-24" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_right"></span> </button> </div> </div> <div class="mb-30 tlr-student-links"> <div class="text-gray-900 p-5 font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mx-10 mb-10"> For Students </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/summary/metaphysics"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/29/84829-050-2FE9BCE1/Aristotle-with-a-Bust-of-Homer-canvas.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Rembrandt: Aristotle with a Bust of Homer" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/summary/metaphysics" >metaphysics summary</a> </div> </div> </div> <div class="mb-30 tlr-related-questions"> <div class="text-gray-900 p-5 pb-0 font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mx-10 mb-15"> Related Questions </div> <ul> <li class="link-gray-900 mb-15"><a class="" href="/question/What-is-Rene-Descartes-known-for">What is René Descartes known for?</a> </li> <li class="link-gray-900 mb-15"><a class="" href="/question/What-was-Rene-Descartess-family-like">What was René Descartes’s family like?</a> </li> <li class="link-gray-900 mb-15"><a class="" href="/question/How-did-Rene-Descartes-die">How did René Descartes die?</a> </li> <li class="link-gray-900 mb-15"><a class="" href="/question/What-did-Hegel-write">What did Hegel write?</a> </li> <li class="link-gray-900 mb-15"><a class="" href="/question/Why-is-Hegel-significant">Why is Hegel significant?</a> </li> </ul> </div> <div class="mb-30 tlr-read-next"> <div class="text-gray-900 p-5 font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mx-10 mb-10"> Read Next </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/list/philosophers-to-know-part-ii"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-131-CFC2DE8A/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), German philosopher. Print published in London, 1812. Profile portrait surrounded by Ouroboros ancient Egyptian-Greek symbolic serpent with tail in mouth devouring itself representing unity of material and spiritual in eternal..." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/list/philosophers-to-know-part-ii" >Philosophers to Know, Part II</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/list/philosophers-to-know-part-i"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/96/142296-131-425C3B45/Aristotle-types-reasoning.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Aristotle (384-322 BC), Ancient Greek philosopher and scientist. One of the most influential philosophers in the history of Western thought, Aristotle established the foundations for the modern scientific method of enquiry. Statue" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/list/philosophers-to-know-part-i" >Philosophers to Know, Part I</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/plato-and-aristotle-how-do-they-differ"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/75/177675-131-B7B445EB/detail-Aristotle-School-of-Athens-Plato-Raphael.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Plato (left) and Aristotle, detail from School of Athens, fresco by Raphael, 1508-11; in the Stanza della Segnatura, the Vatican. Plato points to the heavens and the realm of Forms, Aristotle to the earth and the realm of things." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/plato-and-aristotle-how-do-they-differ" >Plato and Aristotle: How Do They Differ?</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/whats-the-difference-between-morality-and-ethics"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/80/191980-131-AC0F1C4B/stones-boulder-top.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Well-balanced of stones on the top of boulder" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/whats-the-difference-between-morality-and-ethics" >What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/aristotle-at-2400"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/62/190562-131-1A9B2031/Aristotle-statue-Stageira-Greece.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Aristotle statue located at Stageira of Greece" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/aristotle-at-2400" >Aristotle at 2,400</a> </div> </div> </div> <div class="mb-30 tlr-discover"> <div class="text-gray-900 p-5 font-serif font-14 font-weight-bold mx-10 mb-10"> Discover </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/is-spontaneous-human-combustion-real"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/195407-131-BF6F47C2/Illustration-Spontaneous-human-combustion.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Illustration for Demystified "Spontaneous human combustion"." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/is-spontaneous-human-combustion-real" >Is Spontaneous Human Combustion Real?</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/nikola-teslas-weird-obsession-with-pigeons"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/13/173513-131-C6E1BD52/mourning-dove-North-America.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="bird. mourning dove. pigeon and dove. Mourning Dove (Zenaida macroura) family Columbidae." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/nikola-teslas-weird-obsession-with-pigeons" >Nikola Tesla's Weird Obsession with Pigeons</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/6-important-mughal-emperors"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/09/172209-131-02E18D09/Shah-Jahan-watercolour-gold-ink-paper-1690.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Shah Jahan. Taj Mahal. Mughal architecture. Emperor Shah Jahan fifth Mughal Emperor (reigned 1628-1658) India, Himachal Pradesh, Basohli or Jammu and Kashmir, Mankot, circa 1690 Drawings; Opaque watercolor, gold, and ink on paper (see notes)" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/6-important-mughal-emperors" >6 Important Mughal Emperors</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/list/10-women-scientists-who-should-be-famous-or-more-famous"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/148438-131-7A2FD02E/Maria-Telkes.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Dr. Maria Telkes, September 4, 1956." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/list/10-women-scientists-who-should-be-famous-or-more-famous" >10 Women Scientists Who Should Be Famous (or More Famous)</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/how-many-countries-are-there-in-the-world"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/27/238527-131-D73B3F08/flagpoles-world-countries.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Flags of the countries of the world (flagpoles)." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/how-many-countries-are-there-in-the-world" >How Many Countries Are There in the World?</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/who-was-the-woman-behind-the-statue-of-liberty"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/61/93061-131-ABCDE075/Statue-of-Liberty-Island-New-York-Bay.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="Statue of Liberty in front of the skyline of Manhattan, New York City, New York." width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/who-was-the-woman-behind-the-statue-of-liberty" >Who Was the Woman Behind the Statue of Liberty?</a> </div> </div> <div class="imagelink-with-image-on-the-side card card-horizontal tlr-img-with-side-link ml-15 link-gray-900 mb-10" > <div class="position-relative card-media" style="flex: 0;"> <a class="ilf-image position-relative" href="/story/the-lost-colony-of-roanoke"> <img loading="lazy" src="https://cdn.britannica.com/39/191439-131-59FE0A72/John-White-word-tree-CROATOAN-Roanoke-Island-1590.jpg?w=200&h=200&c=crop" alt="The Lost Colony of Roanoke, North Carolina, where 115 people mysteriously disappeared c. 1590. John White discovers the word Croatoan carved onto a tree upon his return to the deserted Roanoke Colony in 1590" width="200" height="200" /> </a> </div> <div class="card-body ilf-content"> <a class="font-weight-semi-bold d-block mb-5 font-16 ilf-title" href="/story/the-lost-colony-of-roanoke" >The Lost Colony of Roanoke</a> </div> </div> </div> </div> </div> </div> <button class="drawerToggle btn position-sticky border btn-xs btn-white btn-circle rounded-sm d-none d-lg-flex " type="button" aria-label="Toggle Drawer"> <em class="material-icons font-18 text-blue" data-icon="keyboard_arrow_left"></em> </button> </div> </div> <div class="col"> <div class="h-100 ml-0 pr-lg-0 "> <div class="h-100 grid gx-0 gx-lg-20"> <div class="h-100 col-sm"> <div class="h-100 infinite-pagination-container d-flex flex-column position-relative"> <div class="position-absolute top-0 h-100 w-100"> <div class="toc-sticky-header d-none d-lg-none bg-gray-50 px-10 px-sm-30 position-sticky w-100 "> <div class="toc-sticky-header-inner-container align-items-center d-flex mx-auto h-100 w-100"> <button class="d-flex d-lg-none btn btn-sm btn-white text-blue border-2 border-gray-100 gtm-mobile-toc-header-button js-sections-button d-lg-none p-10"> <em class="material-icons my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="toc"></em> Contents </button> <div class="header-ai-ask-button-placeholder"></div> <div class="header-ai-summarize-button-placeholder"></div> </div> </div> </div> <div class="grey-box w-100 grey-box-top"> <div class="grey-box-content mx-auto w-100"> <script type="application/ld+json"> { "@context" : "https://schema.org", "@type" : "BreadcrumbList", "itemListElement" : [ { "@type" : "ListItem", "position" : 1, "item" : { "@id" : "https://www.britannica.com/browse/Philosophy-Religion", "name": "Philosophy & Religion" } } , { "@type" : "ListItem", "position" : 2, "item" : { "@id" : "https://www.britannica.com/browse/Philosophical-Issues", "name": "Philosophical Issues" } } ] } </script> <nav class="breadcrumb mt-20"> <span class="breadcrumb-item "> <a class="link-gray-600" href="/browse/Philosophy-Religion">Philosophy & Religion</a> </span> <span class="breadcrumb-item "> <a class="link-gray-600" href="/browse/Philosophical-Issues">Philosophical Issues</a> </span> </nav> <div class="page2ref-true topic-content topic-type-REGULAR" data-student-article="false"> <script class="page-description-json" type="application/json"> { "url": "/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics", "shareUrl": "https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics", "browserTitle": "Metaphysics - Problems in metaphysics", "firstTopicPage": false, "topicId":377923 } </script> <div class="reading-channel"> <div class="topic-header"> <div class="d-flex align-items-top justify-content-between"> <div class="d-flex flex-column"> <div> <div> <h1>Problems in metaphysics</h1></div> <div class="in-container"> <em class="material-icons in-arrow" data-icon="subdirectory_arrow_right"></em> <span class="in-bc">in</span><a class="in-link" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics">metaphysics</a> </div> </div> </div> </div> <div class="d-none d-sm-flex flex-row"> <div class="mr-10 mb-15"> <button class="ai-ask-button btn border-2 btn-sm js-inline-ai-ask-button btn-outline-red-400 border-red-400"> Ask the Chatbot a Question </button> </div> <div class="d-block md-topic-tools qa-action-buttons mb-15" data-topic-id="377923"> <button class="js-tooltip btn btn-sm btn-outline-blue border pr-10 border-2 text-nowrap" > <em class="material-icons md-icon ml-n10 my-n5 mr-5" data-icon="more_vert"></em> More Actions </button> <div class="md-more-popover popover popover-sm p-0 font-14 z-1"> <div> <button class="js-print-modal-button js-modal gtm-topic-tool btn btn-sm btn-link gtm-topic-tool font-weight-bold btn-link" data-modal="[data-topic-id=377923] .md-print-modal" > <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="print"></em> Print </button> <div class="md-print-modal size-lg d-none"> <div class="md-modal-body"> <div class="h2 font-serif d-flex align-items-center pb-15 border-bottom"> <em class="material-icons text-blue mr-10">print</em> Print </div> <div class="mt-20 mb-10"> Please select which sections you would like to print: </div> <form action="/print/article/377923" method="post" target="_blank" rel="noopener"> <div class="print-box-items"> <ul class="list-unstyled"> <li><label><input class="mr-10" type="checkbox" name="sequence[]" value="0">Table Of Contents</label></li> </ul> </div> <input type="submit" class="btn btn-blue md-disabled" value="Print" /> </form> </div> </div> </div> <div> <button class="js-modal qa-cite-modal-button btn btn-sm btn-link gtm-topic-tool font-weight-bold btn-link" data-modal="[data-topic-id=377923] .md-cite-modal"> <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="verified"></em> Cite </button> <div class="md-cite-modal size-lg d-none"> <div class="md-modal-body"> <div class="h2 font-serif d-flex align-items-center pb-15 border-bottom mb-15"> <em class="material-icons text-blue mr-10">verified</em>Cite </div> <div class="font-serif"> While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions. </div> <div class="label mt-20 mb-10">Select Citation Style</div> <select class="js-citation-format-select form-select"> <option selected value="mla">MLA</option> <option value="apa">APA</option> <option value="chicago">Chicago Manual of Style</option> </select> <div class="citation font-serif border rounded p-15 mt-20" data-authors="Inwagen, Peter van, Grayling, A.C., Walsh, William Henry, Zimmerman, Dean W., Wolin, Richard" data-authors-initial="Inwagen, P.V., Grayling, A., Walsh, W.H., Zimmerman, D.W., Wolin, R." data-title="metaphysics" data-published-date="9 Dec. 2024" data-url="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics" > <div class="citation-text"></div> </div> <button class="js-copy-citation-button mt-20 btn btn-xs btn-outline-blue border shadow-sm pr-10" > <em class="material-icons md-icon ml-n10 my-n5 mr-5" data-icon="file_copy"></em> <span class="js-citation-status-text">Copy Citation</span> </button> </div> </div> </div> <div> <button class="js-share-modal-button js-modal btn btn-sm btn-link gtm-topic-tool font-weight-bold btn-link" data-modal="[data-topic-id=377923] .md-share-modal"> <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="share"></em> Share </button> <div class="md-share-modal size-lg d-none qa-share-modal"> <div class="md-modal-body"> <div class="h2 font-serif d-flex align-items-center pb-15 border-bottom"> <em class="material-icons text-blue mr-10" data-icon="share"></em> Share </div> <div class="label my-20">Share to social media</div> <div class="md-social-toolbar-circle d-flex align-items-start inverted" data-value="share" title="metaphysics" data-url="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics" > <a class="social-icon facebook justify-content-center d-flex align-items-center align-self-center" data-provider="facebook" href="https://www.facebook.com/BRITANNICA/" target="_blank" rel="noopener"><span>Facebook</span></a> <a class="social-icon x justify-content-center d-flex align-items-center align-self-center" data-provider="x" href="https://x.com/britannica" target="_blank" rel="noopener"><span>X</span></a> </div> <div class="label pt-20 mt-20 mb-5 border-top">URL</div> <a class="font-serif text-truncate d-inline-block" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics">https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics</a> </div> </div> </div> <div> <button class="js-feedback-modal-button js-modal btn btn-sm btn-link gtm-topic-tool font-weight-bold btn-link" data-modal=".md-feedback-modal"> <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="message"></em> Feedback </button> </div> <div> <button class="qa-external-website-modal-button js-modal btn btn-sm btn-link gtm-topic-tool font-weight-bold btn-link" data-modal="[data-topic-id=377923] .md-websites-modal"> <em class="material-icons md-icon ml-n10 mr-5" data-icon="link"></em> External Websites </button> </div> </div> <div class="md-feedback-modal size-lg d-none"> <div class="md-modal-body"> <div class="h2 font-serif pb-15 border-bottom"> Feedback </div> <form method="post" action="/submission/feedback/377923"> <div class="my-20"> Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login). </div> <div class="type-menu"> <label for="feedback-type" class="label mb-10">Feedback Type</label> <select id="feedback-type" class="form-select mb-30" name="feedbackTypeId" required> <option value="" selected="selected">Select a type (Required)</option> <option value="1">Factual Correction</option> <option value="2">Spelling/Grammar Correction</option> <option value="3">Link Correction</option> <option value="4">Additional Information</option> <option value="5">Other</option> </select> </div> <label for="feedback" class="label mb-10">Your Feedback</label> <textarea id="feedback" class="form-control mb-30" name="feedback" maxlength="3000" rows="7" required></textarea> <button class="btn btn-blue" type="submit">Submit Feedback</button> </form> <div class="success-messaging d-none mt-30"> <div class="title">Thank you for your feedback</div> <p>Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.</p> </div> </div> </div> <div class="md-websites-modal size-lg d-none"> <div class="md-modal-body"> <div class="h2 font-serif pb-15 border-bottom font-weight-bold"> External Websites </div> <div class="pb-20"> <ul class="list-unstyled mt-20 lh-lg"> <li><a class="external" href="https://spot.colorado.edu/~tooley/Overview4360-5360.pdf" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">University of Colorado Boulder - Metaphysics - An Overview</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://www.philosophybasics.com/branch_metaphysics.html" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">The Basics of Philosophy - Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://www.academia.edu/36824154/MARTIN_HEIDEGGER_OVERCOMING_METAPHYSICS" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">Academia - Martin Heidegger: overcoming Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://open.library.okstate.edu/introphilosophy/chapter/__unknown__/" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">OpenOKState - An Introduction to Aristotle's Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/overview/metaphysics/v-1" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://human.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Philosophy/It's_Funny_'Cause_It's_True_(Henrigillis_and_Gimbel)/02%3A_Metaphysics" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">Humanities LibreTexts - Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaphysics/" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/leibniz-modal/" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Leibniz's Modal Metaphysics</a></li> <li><a class="external" href="https://royalsocietypublishing.org/doi/10.1098/rsfs.2016.0148" target="_blank" rel="noopener ">The Royal Society Publishing - Interface Focus - The metaphysics of evolution</a></li> </ul> </div> </div> </div> </div> </div> <div class="toc-header-marker"></div> <button class="ai-ask-button btn border-2 js-header-ai-ask-button d-none btn-sm btn-outline-red-400 border-red-400 mr-0 mr-lg-10 ml-5 ml-sm-10 ml-lg-0 p-10"> Ask the Chatbot a Question </button> <div class="md-byline module-spacing "> <div class="font-serif font-12"> <span class="written-by text-gray-700"> Written by </span> <div class="editor-popover popover p-0"> <a class="d-block p-20 qa-editor-popup gtm-byline font-12 byline-contributor" href="/contributor/Peter-van-Inwagen/6110" > <div class="editor-title font-16 font-weight-bold">Peter van Inwagen</div> <div class="editor-description font-12 font-serif mt-5 clamp-description text-black">John Cardinal O'Hara Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame. Author of <em>Ontology, Identity, and Modality</em> and others.</div> </a> <div data-popper-arrow></div> </div> <span class="btn btn-link editor-link p-0 qa-byline-link gtm-byline font-12 byline-contributor text-decoration-underline"> Peter van Inwagen</span>, <div class="editor-popover popover p-0"> <a class="d-block p-20 qa-editor-popup gtm-byline font-12 byline-contributor" href="/contributor/AC-Grayling/1140" > <div class="editor-title font-16 font-weight-bold">A.C. Grayling</div> <div class="editor-description font-12 font-serif mt-5 clamp-description text-black">Lecturer in Philosophy, Birbeck College, University of London. Senior Research Fellow, St. Anne's College, University of Oxford. Author of <i>An Introduction to Philosophical Logic</i> and others.</div> </a> <div data-popper-arrow></div> </div> <span class="btn btn-link editor-link p-0 qa-byline-link gtm-byline font-12 byline-contributor text-decoration-underline"> A.C. Grayling</span><span class="text-gray-700 mx-5">•</span><a class="see-all border-gray-700 gtm-byline" rel="nofollow" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/additional-info#contributors">All</a> </div> <div class="font-serif font-12 text-gray-700"> <span class="qa-fact-checked-by">Fact-checked by</span> <div class="editor-popover popover p-0"> <a class="d-block p-20 qa-editor-popup font-12" href="/editor/The-Editors-of-Encyclopaedia-Britannica/4419" > <div class="editor-title font-16 font-weight-bold">The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica</div> <div class="editor-description font-12 font-serif mt-5 text-black">Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. They write new content and verify and edit content received from contributors.</div> </a> <div data-popper-arrow></div> </div> <span class="btn btn-link editor-link p-0 qa-byline-link font-12 "> The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica</span></div> <div class="last-updated font-12 font-serif"> <a class="byline-edit-history" href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/additional-info#history" rel="nofollow">Article History</a> </div></div> </div> <button class="d-flex d-lg-none btn btn-outline-blue border rounded-sm shadow-sm mobile-toc-button gtm-mobile-toc-inline-button d-none d-sm-block js-sections-inline-button module-spacing btn d-lg-none"> <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="toc"></em> Table of Contents </button> <div class="d-flex d-sm-none flex-row"> <button class="d-flex d-lg-none btn btn-outline-blue border rounded-sm shadow-sm mobile-toc-button gtm-mobile-toc-inline-button js-sections-inline-button module-spacing"> <em class="material-icons mr-5 ml-n10 my-n5 md-icon" data-icon="toc"></em> Table of Contents </button> <button class="ai-ask-button btn border-2 ai-ask-button btn border-2 module-spacing btn-sm js-inline-ai-ask-button btn-outline-red-400 border-red-400 p-10 ml-5"> Ask the Chatbot a Question </button> </div> <div class="js-qf-module qf-module px-40 px-sm-20 py-15 mx-auto module-spacing font-14 bg-gray-50 rounded"> <div class="facts-list mt-10"> <div class=""> <div class="js-fact mb-10 line-clamp clamp-3"> <dl> <dt>Key People: </dt> <dd><a href="/biography/Aristotle" topicid="34560">Aristotle</a></dd> <dd><a href="/biography/Plato" topicid="464109">Plato</a></dd> <dd><a href="/biography/Immanuel-Kant" topicid="311398">Immanuel Kant</a></dd> <dd><a href="/biography/Georg-Wilhelm-Friedrich-Hegel" topicid="259378">Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel</a></dd> <dd><a href="/biography/Rene-Descartes" topicid="158787">René Descartes</a></dd> </dl> <button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-gray-50" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"> <em class="js-content link-blue">(Show more)</em> </button> </div> </div> <div class=""> <div class="js-fact mb-10 line-clamp clamp-3"> <dl> <dt>Related Topics: </dt> <dd><a href="/topic/ontology-metaphysics" topicid="429409">ontology</a></dd> <dd><a href="/topic/problem-of-universals" topicid="2233338">problem of universals</a></dd> <dd><a href="/topic/mind-body-problem" topicid="2233337">mind-body problem</a></dd> <dd><a href="/topic/hylomorphism" topicid="279305">hylomorphism</a></dd> <dd><a href="/topic/personalism" topicid="452990">personalism</a></dd> </dl> <button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-gray-50" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"> <em class="js-content link-blue">(Show more)</em> </button> </div> <div class="text-center"> <a class="btn btn-sm btn-link p-0" href="/facts/metaphysics"> See all related content </a> </div> </div> </div> </div><!--[BEFORE-ARTICLE]--><span class="marker before-article"></span><!--[H3]--><span class="marker h3"></span><section data-level="1" id="ref15809"> <!--[TOC]--> <section data-level="2" id="ref344383"> <h2 class="h2">The reality of the external world</h2> <section data-level="3" id="ref344384"> <h2 class="h3">The problem in early modern philosophy</h2> <!--[PREMOD1]--><span class="marker PREMOD1 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Although <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/sensation" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">sensations</a> (i.e., the conscious experiences that result from stimulation of the sense organs) are mental events, they seem to most people to be a source of information—fallible, perhaps, but in the main reliable—about a nonmental world, the world of material or physical objects, which <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="constitutes" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/constitutes" data-type="MW">constitutes</a> the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="environment" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/environment" data-type="MW">environment</a> of the perceiver. Regarding that “external world,” many philosophers have attempted to answer the following related questions: Is there an external world? If there is, do the senses provide reliable information about it? If they do, do human beings know—or can they come to know—what the external world is like? If they can, what exactly is the source or basis of that knowledge? To attempt to answer such questions is to address the problem of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/reality-of-the-external-world" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">reality of the external world</a>.</p><!--[MOD1]--><span class="marker MOD1 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD2]--><span class="marker PREMOD2 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="238240" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-050-439A37F8/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/238240"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-050-439A37F8/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-050-439A37F8/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg?w=300" alt="René Descartes" data-width="1212" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/95/190395-050-439A37F8/Rene-Descartes-oil-painting-Frans-Hals-1649.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/238240">René Descartes</a><span>René Descartes, oil on oak by Frans Hals, c. 1649; in the National Gallery of Denmark.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">That problem belongs entirely to modern (that is, postmedieval) philosophy; no <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Western-philosophy/Ancient-Greek-and-Roman-philosophy#ref8565" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">ancient</a> or <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Western-philosophy/Medieval-philosophy#ref8638" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">medieval</a> philosopher so much as considered any of the questions mentioned in the previous paragraph. First explored by the French philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Rene-Descartes" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">René Descartes</a> (1596–1650), it was not regarded as fundamental or especially important—i.e., as a problem that every philosophical system with any <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="pretense" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/pretense" data-type="EB">pretense</a> to comprehensiveness was obliged to address—until the work of the Anglo-Irish philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/George-Berkeley" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">George Berkeley</a> (1685–1753) became widely known. Berkeley devised very able and ingenious arguments for a thoroughgoing form of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/idealism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">idealism</a>, according to which nothing exists but ideas (i.e., sensations and mental images), things composed of ideas, and the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/mind" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">minds</a> within which ideas exist. Although few philosophers accepted Berkeley’s doctrine—his arguments were <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="notorious" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/notorious" data-type="MW">notorious</a> rather than famous—it was generally considered important that it should be refuted. The typical attitude of philosophers of the 18th century to the problem of the reality of the external world was well summarized by the German Enlightenment philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Immanuel-Kant" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Immanuel Kant</a> (1724–1804), who wrote (in a footnote to the introduction of the second edition [1787] of his <em><a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Immanuel-Kant" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Critique of Pure Reason</a></em>):</p><!--[MOD2]--><span class="marker MOD2 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>It remains a scandal to philosophy, and to human reason in general, that it is necessary to take the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/existence" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">existence</a> of things outside us…merely on faith, and, if anyone should happen to doubt it, no adequate proof can be produced to oppose him.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD4]--><span class="marker PREMOD4 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Descartes’s formulation of the problem is presented in his <em>Meditationes de Prima Philosophia</em> (1641; <em>Meditations on First Philosophy</em>)—a record, in the form of a first-person narrative, of its author’s search for an absolutely reliable foundation of human knowledge. Descartes assumed that each person, in order to have knowledge, required such a foundation, and he further assumed that the foundation of each person’s knowledge would be a set of propositions whose <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/truth-philosophy-and-logic" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">truth</a> it was impossible for that person to doubt and on the basis of which additional propositions (further knowledge) could be inferred. He proposed to demonstrate to each reader of the <em>Meditations</em> how that reader could find such a set of propositions by using himself, Descartes, as an example. He therefore set out to identify those propositions that it was impossible for him to doubt. Those propositions, Descartes argued, were precisely those that he could be certain of even in the following worst-case scenario: “I will suppose that…some <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="malicious" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/malicious" data-type="MW">malicious</a> demon of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies to deceive me.” In such a case, Descartes decided, what he could be certain of (besides a few self-evident necessary truths, like “1 + 1 = 2” and “Things equal to the same thing are equal to each other”) would be only his own present existence as a <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">thinking</a>, sensing being and his present thoughts and sensations. Such was the foundation upon which the edifice of his knowledge was to be constructed. The “ground floor” of the building would be a proof that the sensations that he had found within himself—sensations that seemed to him to represent physical or material objects like the body he animated and the pen in his fingers and the paper and writing table before him (each of them with a determinate set of physical properties)—were veridical (truth-telling). If Descartes’s sensations were veridical, then an external world would exist, since “an external world” is no more than a name for the totality of objects of the kind (material or physical) whose existence Descartes’s sensations testified to. And if Descartes knew that his sensations were veridical, he would know that there was an external world, and he would know that it was (locally, at least) more or less as his sensations indicated that it was. (It should be noted, however, that Descartes, writing in Latin, used neither the word <em>veridicus</em> [“veridical”] nor any phrase that could be translated as “the external world.”)</p><!--[MOD4]--><span class="marker MOD4 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD5]--><span class="marker PREMOD5 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The central argument of the <em>Meditations</em> aims to establish the conclusion that its author’s sensations are veridical. The core of the argument consists of two subordinate arguments, each of which seeks to prove the existence of a perfect being—that is, of God. The purpose of the current discussion does not require an exposition of those arguments; it <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="suffices" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/suffices" data-type="MW">suffices</a> to point out that Descartes maintained that each of the subordinate arguments is valid and that one can recognize their validity without having to assume that one’s sensations are veridical.</p><div class="module-spacing"> </div><!--[MOD5]--><span class="marker MOD5 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD6]--><span class="marker PREMOD6 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Having demonstrated (to his own satisfaction) the existence of a perfect being, Descartes proceeded to argue that if his (Descartes’s) sensations were not veridical, the perfect being just established—the creator of all things and hence of all sensations—would be a deceiver. His argument concludes with the observation that deceit is an imperfection and hence incompatible with the nature of a perfect being. The <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="hypothesis" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hypothesis" data-type="MW">hypothesis</a> that his sensations are not veridical thus leads to a contradiction, from which it follows that his sensations are veridical after all (<em>see</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/reductio-ad-absurdum" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">reductio ad absurdum</a>). Descartes assumes that each of his readers will be able to establish the same conclusion with respect to the reader’s own sensations.</p><!--[MOD6]--><span class="marker MOD6 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD7]--><span class="marker PREMOD7 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Very few philosophers have found the argument of the <em>Meditations</em> convincing, if for no other reason than that very few of them have been convinced by either of the subordinate arguments for the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/existence-of-God" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">existence of God</a> (and theists have been hardly less critical of those arguments than atheists.) Moreover, very few philosophers have supposed that some other argument for the veridicality of sensations or for the existence of an external world succeeds where Descartes’s argument fails. (The above quotation from Kant reflected his belief that he had presented a new, and of course successful, argument for the reality of the external world. His argument, however, is notoriously obscure, and in any case it relies so extensively on the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="elaborate" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/elaborate" data-type="EB">elaborate</a> philosophical apparatus that is unique to <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Kantianism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Kantian philosophy</a> that it is hardly possible for anyone who is not a full-fledged Kantian to accept it.)</p><!--[MOD7]--><span class="marker MOD7 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="3" id="ref344385"> <h2 class="h3">Berkeleyan idealism</h2> <!--[PREMOD8]--><span class="marker PREMOD8 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="68890" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-050-572BA52D/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/68890"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-050-572BA52D/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-050-572BA52D/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg?w=300" alt="George Berkeley" data-width="1179" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/07/29907-050-572BA52D/George-Berkeley-detail-oil-painting-John-Smibert-1732.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/68890">George Berkeley</a><span>George Berkeley, detail of an oil painting by John Smibert, c. 1732; in the National Portrait Gallery, London.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">Although Berkeley denied the existence of anything besides ideas, things composed of ideas, and the minds within which ideas exist, he did not explicitly deny the existence of objects such as “the body Descartes animated,” “the pen in his fingers,” and “the paper and writing table before him.” Berkeley instead affirmed the existence of those objects but insisted that they were composed of ideas. His argument was straightforward. Adapted to the present case, its central point can be formulated as follows:</p><!--[MOD8]--><span class="marker MOD8 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>Take the whiteness of the sheet of paper before Descartes—or its (perceived) shape. Those properties cannot exist outside the mind—that is, outside anyone’s <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/mind" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">mind</a>. Thus, the properties of a sheet of paper exist in the mind. Furthermore, there is nothing more to a thing than its properties—in particular, there is no imperceptible “substrate” in which properties “inhere,” as the English philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/John-Locke" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">John Locke</a> (1632–1704) held. (If there were such a thing, how would anyone know about it, given that all knowledge is <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="derived" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/derived" data-type="EB">derived</a> from <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/perception" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">perception</a>, and the substrate is by definition imperceptible?) Therefore, sheets of paper and all other objects of the kind that philosophers call “material” exist only in the mind. Indeed, there is nothing wrong with anyone’s calling the sheet of paper material, if by that word the speaker means that it is extended in space and impenetrable (it cannot be penetrated by another extended object without suffering damage). But extension and impenetrability are properties like any other, and as such they exist only in the mind.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD10]--><span class="marker PREMOD10 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">In a sense, therefore, Berkeley accepted the existence of an external world, because he affirmed the existence of “material” objects, of which the external world is ordinarily said to be composed. Moreover, for Berkeley, there are things that exist partly or wholly outside each person’s mind—namely, ideas that are not in that person’s mind, and minds that are not identical to that person’s mind. But most philosophers who speak of the problem of the reality of the external world would deny that Berkeley’s idealism is consistent with the reality of an external world as they understand that phrase. Kant is a case in point. His proof of the existence of “things outside us” occurs, in the <em>Critique of Pure Reason</em>, under the heading “Refutation of Idealism,” and by “idealism” he meant Berkeleyan idealism (or “dogmatic” idealism, as he also called it—that is, an idealism that is defended on the basis of <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="metaphysical" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/metaphysical" data-type="MW">metaphysical</a> reasoning of the kind that Kant’s <em>Critique</em> was designed to refute). Indeed, almost all philosophers who have used the phrase “external world” would join Kant in regarding Berkeleyan idealism as inconsistent with the reality of an external world. Specifically, they would insist that at least one of the two following statements (both of which Berkeley affirmed) must be false:</p><!--[MOD10]--><span class="marker MOD10 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Extension and impenetrability exist only in the mind.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. A thing is material if and only if it is both extended and impenetrable.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD13]--><span class="marker PREMOD13 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Berkeley never used the phrase “external world,” and he might well have said that philosophers who wished to use that term of art were free to use it in any sense that pleased them. He would, however, have vehemently rejected the thesis that either statement 1 or statement 2 must be false. His argument against that thesis would have proceeded along the following lines:</p><!--[MOD13]--><span class="marker MOD13 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>Statement 2 is true by definition, so its denial is nonsensical. As to statement 1, <em>extension</em> must mean either visual extension (the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/quality-philosophy" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">quality</a> called “extension” when one is speaking of ideas presented by the sense of sight) or <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="tactile" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/tactile" data-type="MW">tactile</a> extension (the quality called “extension” when one is speaking of ideas presented by the sense of touch). It follows that neither visual extension nor tactile extension can exist outside the mind. Similar reasoning applies to the term <em>impenetrability</em>. Therefore, neither extension nor impenetrability exists outside the mind; i.e., statement 1 is true.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD15]--><span class="marker PREMOD15 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Because Berkeley explicitly affirmed the existence of “material” objects and implicitly accepted the existence of an “external world,” the problem of the reality of an external world cannot simply be identified with the question of the truth of Berkeleyan idealism (i.e., the external world is real if and only if Berkeleyan idealism is false). As indicated above, however, most philosophers regard the problem of the reality of the external world as practically equivalent to the question of the truth of Berkeleyan idealism, in part because they reject Berkeley’s <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="eccentric" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/eccentric" data-type="MW">eccentric</a> understandings of the terms in which the problem is typically formulated.</p><!--[MOD15]--><span class="marker MOD15 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="3" id="ref344386"> <h2 class="h3">The problem in 20th-century and later philosophy</h2> <!--[PREMOD16]--><span class="marker PREMOD16 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="13074" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-050-D9456DAA/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/13074"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-050-D9456DAA/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-050-D9456DAA/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg?w=300" alt="G.E. Moore" data-width="1404" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/78/2778-050-D9456DAA/GE-Moore-William-Orpen-detail-pencil-drawing.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/13074">G.E. Moore</a><span>G.E. Moore, detail of a pencil drawing by William Orpen; in the National Portrait Gallery, London.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">In his famous 1939 British Academy lecture, “Proof of an External World,” the English philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/G-E-Moore" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">G.E. Moore</a> (1873–1958) offered a very simple “proof” of the reality of an external world. The importance of the proof, however, lies not so much in the proof itself as in certain arguments that Moore presented to establish that it was indeed a proof. The proof was essentially this: Moore displayed one of his hands to his audience and said, “Here is one hand.” He then displayed his other hand and said, “and here is another.” He continued by presenting a careful and very precise piece of reasoning intended to establish the conclusion that the “here-is-a-hand” argument was indeed a proof of the reality of an external world—that, considered in relation to the proposition “there is an external world,” the here-is-a-hand argument satisfied all the requirements for being a proof that anyone could reasonably impose. One essential <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="premise" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/premise" data-type="MW">premise</a> of the reasoning by which Moore claimed to have demonstrated that the here-is-a-hand argument was a proof of the existence of an external world was the assertion that he and everyone in his audience knew that there was a pair of hands before them.</p><!--[MOD16]--><span class="marker MOD16 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD17]--><span class="marker PREMOD17 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Notwithstanding the blunt simplicity of Moore’s proof—a characteristic that struck some philosophers as slightly absurd—it is undeniable that Moore regarded the problem of the reality of the external world with deep seriousness. In his view, “Is there an external world?” is a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="legitimate" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/legitimate" data-type="MW">legitimate</a> philosophical question, just as “Did the human species die out in the 13th century?” is a legitimate historical question. Most later philosophers, however, differed from Moore on that point. In various ways, they attempted to show that the question was not genuinely philosophical or that it was not even a real question but instead a form of nonsense. Those philosophers held that the historical problem of the reality of the external world was the product of fundamental misunderstandings of the nature of human knowledge, the nature of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/language" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">language</a>, or even the nature of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/human-being" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">human being</a> (i.e., the human mode of being).</p><!--[MOD17]--><span class="marker MOD17 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD18]--><span class="marker PREMOD18 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Such <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="criticism" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/criticism" data-type="MW">criticism</a> was characteristic of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/logical-positivism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">logical positivism</a>, an important school of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/analytic-philosophy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">analytic philosophy</a> that flourished between the two World Wars. For the logical positivists, the sentences “There is an external world” and “There is not an external world” are both literally meaningless, as are many other metaphysical utterances. That position is a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="consequence" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/consequence" data-type="EB">consequence</a> of the logical positivists’ “verifiability principle,” according to which a sentence is literally meaningful if and only if it is either in principle empirically verifiable (or falsifiable) or a <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/tautology" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">tautology</a>. Because no possible experience (no possible experiment or observation) could either prove or disprove that there is an external world, all statements about its existence or nonexistence are nonsensical.</p><!--[MOD18]--><span class="marker MOD18 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD19]--><span class="marker PREMOD19 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The Austrian-born philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Ludwig-Wittgenstein" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Ludwig Wittgenstein</a> (1889–1951) and the German philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Martin-Heidegger-German-philosopher" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Martin Heidegger</a> (1889–1976), who are widely regarded as the two most important philosophers of the 20th century, believed that the question of the reality of the external world could be meaningfully posed only within philosophical traditions that were founded upon, and perpetuated, misapprehensions of some fundamental aspect of human experience or the human condition. For Wittgenstein, the misapprehensions concerned human language and thought; for Heidegger, they concerned human being.</p><!--[MOD19]--><span class="marker MOD19 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD20]--><span class="marker PREMOD20 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Wittgenstein’s famous “private-language argument,” which appears in his posthumously published work <em>Philosophische Untersuchungen</em> (1953; <em>Philosophical Investigations</em>), can be read as implying that if there were no external world (a term, however, that Wittgenstein did not use), all language would be without meaning—from which it would follow that the question “Is there an external world?” is itself meaningless unless there is an external world. If Wittgenstein is correct, the question “Is there an external world?” is effectively answered in its being posed, as are (for example) “Is there such a thing as language?” and “Does anyone ever ask a question?” In a later work <em>Über Gewissheit</em> (1969; <em>On Certainty</em>), Wittgenstein insisted on a radical distinction between certitude and knowledge, holding that the former is not merely a surer form of the latter. Instead, certitude is the background or setting in which the “language games” of knowing, doubting, and believing (among others) take place. Ultimately, what is certain is that which is presupposed or taken for granted in the social activities of a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="community" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/community" data-type="MW">community</a>.</p><!--[MOD20]--><span class="marker MOD20 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD21]--><span class="marker PREMOD21 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="11500" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/11500"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg?w=300" alt="Martin Heidegger" data-width="217" data-height="300" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/38/11138-004-6699034E/Martin-Heidegger.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/11500">Martin Heidegger</a><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">In his early masterpiece <em>Sein und Zeit</em> (1927; <em>Being and Time</em>), Heidegger characterized the philosophy of Descartes—and, by extension, all of modern <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">epistemology</a>—as positing a division between an “inner” world of subjective mental experiences and a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="hypothetical" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hypothetical" data-type="MW">hypothetical</a> “outer” world of objective material things. The two worlds were in principle completely independent of each other (the existence of the one did not imply the existence of the other), and the only possible relation between the two was that of “representation,” whereby certain elements of mental experience could represent or correspond to certain features of the objective material world. The task of philosophy, according to the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Cartesianism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Cartesian</a> <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="conception" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/conception" data-type="MW">conception</a> (as Heidegger and others interpreted it), was to show how or to what extent the relation of representation might be veridical.</p><!--[MOD21]--><span class="marker MOD21 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD22]--><span class="marker PREMOD22 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">According to Heidegger, however, the two “worlds” were not at all independent; to the contrary, each was a distorted <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/abstraction" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">abstraction</a> of a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="primordial" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/primordial" data-type="MW">primordial</a> and unified <em>Dasein</em> (literally, “being-there”)—the mode of human being—which was inherently already involved with and caught up in a world that the Cartesian tradition had misconceived as independent of isolated human subjects. Commenting on Kant’s “scandal to philosophy,” Heidegger wrote (in <em>Being and Time</em>): “The ‘scandal to philosophy’ does not lie in the fact that this proof has not <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="yet" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/yet" data-type="EB">yet</a> been given, but rather in the fact that such proofs are continually expected and attempted.”</p><!--[MOD22]--><span class="marker MOD22 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD23]--><span class="marker PREMOD23 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">It should be remarked, however, that in the 20th century—Heidegger’s century—such proofs were not actually continually expected or attempted. Even Moore’s “proof” was best understood not as a genuine attempt to prove the existence of an external world but rather as a way of raising a pointed philosophical question about what the skeptical demand for a proof of the reality of the external world really amounted to. And that question is, “Why does a certain trivial exercise (presenting one’s hands to an audience and saying, ‘Here is one hand’ and ‘here is another’) <em>not</em> count as a proof of the reality of an external world?”</p><!--[MOD23]--><span class="marker MOD23 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD24]--><span class="marker PREMOD24 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The remarkable revival of <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="metaphysics" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/metaphysics" data-type="MW">metaphysics</a> among <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="analytic" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/analytic" data-type="MW">analytic</a> philosophers in the last quarter of the 20th century did nothing to reawaken interest in the question of the reality of the external world. Subsequent analytic metaphysics was concerned either with problems that had no bearing on that question (e.g., problems regarding <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/modality" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">modality</a>, <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/ontology-metaphysics" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">ontology</a>, and the nature of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/time" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">time</a>) or with questions about the metaphysics of the physical or material world. (Metaphysicians writing on the metaphysics of the material world have been content to take its existence for granted and have devoted themselves entirely to questions about the kinds of objects it <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="comprises" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/comprises" data-type="MW">comprises</a> and their properties.) The sole exception to that generalization is provided by a few defenses of idealism, such as the essay “Idealism Vindicated” (2007), by the American philosopher Robert Merrihew Adams, and <em>A World for Us: The Case for Phenomenalistic Idealism</em> (2008), by the English philosopher John Foster.</p><!--[MOD24]--><span class="marker MOD24 mod-inline"></span> </section> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344387"> <h2 class="h2">Mind and body</h2> <!--[PREMOD25]--><span class="marker PREMOD25 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Human beings seem to have properties of two quite different kinds: physical properties, such as size and weight, and mental properties, such as feeling pain or believing that Tokyo is the capital of Japan, which imply sensation or thought. Among the properties of persons, mental properties have seemed to many philosophers to be in some sense deeper or more fundamental than physical properties. That <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/idea" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">idea</a> is supported by a famous observation made by Descartes: that whereas it is at least conceivable that people should be mistaken about their physical properties, it is inconceivable that their mental properties should be anything other than what they seem to them to be.</p><!--[MOD25]--><span class="marker MOD25 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD26]--><span class="marker PREMOD26 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">There are many theories about the existence of and relation between physical and mental properties. At one extreme there are idealists, who deny the existence of physical properties, and at the other there are <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/behaviourism-psychology" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">behaviourists</a> and <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/analytic-philosophy/Eliminative-materialism#ref242080" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">eliminative materialists</a>, who deny the existence of mental properties (<em>see below</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Cartesianism#ref15845" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Types of metaphysical theory: Materialism</a>). Most philosophers, however, believe that properties of both kinds exist. Philosophical theories of mind may be categorized according to the ways in which they conceive of the relation between physical and mental properties and according to their <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="implications" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/implications" data-type="MW">implications</a> regarding the so-called <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/mind-body-problem" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">mind-body problem</a>, the problem of explaining how mental events arise from or interact with physical events. Historically, three types of theory have been most influential: psychophysical monism, property <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/dualism-philosophy" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">dualism</a>, and psychophysical dualism.</p><!--[MOD26]--><span class="marker MOD26 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD27]--><span class="marker PREMOD27 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">According to psychophysical monism, the physical and mental properties of human beings are properties of the same thing: of their bodies or of parts of their bodies, such as the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/cerebral-cortex" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">cerebral cortex</a> or the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/nervous-system" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">nervous system</a>. Psychophysical monists also believe that the mental properties of a thing are completely determined by its physical properties. Thus, a perfect physical duplicate of a thinking, feeling human being would, of necessity, have exactly the same mental properties as that human being. Psychophysical monists are almost all <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="proponents" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/proponents" data-type="EB">proponents</a> of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-soul-and-personal-identity#ref283968" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">identity theory</a>, according to which mental events (i.e., the gain or loss of a mental property) are the same as or identical to physical events (i.e., the gain or loss of a physical property).</p><!--[MOD27]--><span class="marker MOD27 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD28]--><span class="marker PREMOD28 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Property dualists agree with psychophysical monists that the physical and mental properties of human beings are properties of the same things (human bodies or their parts) but reject the other thesis of the monists, that the physical properties of a thing necessarily determine its mental properties. They hold that it is at least metaphysically possible to assume that there are two beings with identical physical properties but different mental properties. That possibility, moreover, implies that mental properties are nonphysical properties—hence the term <em>property dualism</em>. The so-called <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/double-aspect-theory" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">double-aspect theory</a> of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Benedict-de-Spinoza" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Benedict de Spinoza</a> (1632–77) and <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Arthur-Schopenhauer" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Arthur Schopenhauer</a> (1788–1860) is probably best categorized as a form of property dualism.</p><!--[MOD28]--><span class="marker MOD28 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD29]--><span class="marker PREMOD29 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">According to psychophysical dualism, the physical properties of human beings are properties of their bodies and the mental properties of human beings are properties of their minds or <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/soul-religion-and-philosophy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">souls</a>—a person’s mind or <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/soul-religion-and-philosophy" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">soul</a> being an immaterial substance wholly distinct from the physical substance that is that person’s body.</p><!--[MOD29]--><span class="marker MOD29 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD30]--><span class="marker PREMOD30 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Among psychophysical dualists, dualistic interactionists hold that the body and the mind interact—that the mind causally affects the body and the body causally affects the mind. Dualistic interactionists seem to be committed to the position that the physical world is not causally closed—i.e., that physical events cannot always be completely explained by reference to earlier physical events and the laws of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/physics-science" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">physics</a>. That position, however, would seem to be inconsistent with the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/conservation-law" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">conservation laws</a> (e.g., <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/conservation-of-energy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">conservation of energy</a> and <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/conservation-of-momentum" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">conservation of momentum</a>) that are fundamental to modern physics.</p><!--[MOD30]--><span class="marker MOD30 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD31]--><span class="marker PREMOD31 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Other psychophysical dualists, known as <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/occasionalism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">occasionalists</a>, have maintained that the apparent causal interaction between mind and body is only apparent: mental and physical changes are coordinated by the direct action of God. (Thus, the act of willing to move one’s arm is an “occasion,” but not a cause, of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/motion-mechanics" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">movement</a> of one’s arm.) Like interactionists, however, occasionalists seem to be committed to the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="thesis" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/thesis" data-type="EB">thesis</a> that there are physical events that cannot be explained in terms of earlier physical events.</p><!--[MOD31]--><span class="marker MOD31 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD32]--><span class="marker PREMOD32 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="200662" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-050-6422D72B/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/200662"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-050-6422D72B/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-050-6422D72B/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg?w=300" alt="Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz" data-width="1245" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/150318-050-6422D72B/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/200662">Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz</a><span>German rationalist philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">The theory of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/preestablished-harmony" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">preestablished harmony</a>, due to <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz</a> (1646–1716), in some ways resembles <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/occasionalism" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">occasionalism</a> but avoids the problem of inconsistency with the closure of the physical world by postulating separate physical and mental realms, each of which unfolds deterministically with the passage of time according to its own laws; the two realms do not interact but have been created (by God) in such a way that they are in perfect harmony with each other.</p><!--[MOD32]--><span class="marker MOD32 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD33]--><span class="marker PREMOD33 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The very unclear position called <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/epiphenomenalistic-materialism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">epiphenomenalism</a> is sometimes categorized as a form of psychophysical dualism according to which the body affects the mind but the mind does not affect the body. Thus, when a human being wills a certain bodily movement and that movement occurs, the movement is caused entirely by prior physical states of the body. The corresponding act of will, however, is also caused by prior physical states. As a result, the act of will seems to its subject to be the cause of the movement. It is, however, probably better to think of epiphenomenalism not as a form of psychophysical dualism but as a form of property dualism according to which both mental events (the gain or loss of a mental property) and physical events (the gain or loss of a physical property) are entirely caused by physical events. Partly because few philosophers have thought of themselves as epiphenomenalists, it is difficult to categorize that view under any familiar type of philosophical theory of mind. The best-known modern epiphenomenalist was the biologist <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Thomas-Henry-Huxley" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Thomas Henry Huxley</a> (1825–95).</p><!--[MOD33]--><span class="marker MOD33 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344388"> <h2 class="h2">Existence</h2> <!--[PREMOD34]--><span class="marker PREMOD34 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Although metaphysicians have had a great deal to say about the existence of various things (e.g., of God, of the soul, of an external world), they have had less to say about existence itself—about the content of the concept of existence or about the meaning of the word <em>existence</em>. They have said enough, however, to make possible a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="taxonomy" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/taxonomy" data-type="MW">taxonomy</a> of theories of existence. Such a taxonomy can be presented as a list of pairs of opposed or contradictory theses about the nature of existence.</p><!--[MOD34]--><span class="marker MOD34 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Some metaphysicians have affirmed, and others have denied, that existence is the same as being. It might seem obvious that “Mountains higher than Mont Blanc exist” and “There are mountains higher than Mont Blanc” are two ways of saying the same thing. But some metaphysicians believe that there are things that do not exist—fictional characters, for example, or the Greek gods. Their position is that, although such things certainly do not exist, the fact that there are such things implies that they have being. If something can “be” without existing, they argue, then existence and being must be distinguished.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. Some metaphysicians have affirmed, and others have denied, that existence is a barren or empty or trivial concept. <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Georg-Wilhelm-Friedrich-Hegel" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">G.W.F. Hegel</a> (1770–1831), for example, referred to being (which he did not distinguish from existence) as “the very poorest and most abstract” of all categories.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Some metaphysicians have affirmed, and others have denied, that the word <em>exist</em> means the same thing in all its applications. For example, mathematicians habitually speak of the “existence” of abstract, mathematical objects like numbers or functions. Metaphysicians, as well as <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/philosophy-of-mathematics" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">philosophers of mathematics</a>, differ on the question of whether <em>existence</em> in such assertions means the same as it does when it is applied to persons and other <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="tangible" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/tangible" data-type="MW">tangible</a>, visible things.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>4. Some metaphysicians have affirmed, and others have denied, that the being (or existence) of one object may be “more perfect,” or “of a higher degree,” than the being (or existence) of another. A classic expression of that idea is the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="analogy" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/analogy" data-type="MW">analogy</a> of the divided line, representing a fourfold <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="hierarchy" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hierarchy" data-type="MW">hierarchy</a> of being, from the <em>Republic</em> of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Plato" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Plato</a> (c. 428–c. 348 <span class="text-smallcaps">bce</span>): images and shadows participate in being very imperfectly, sensible objects less imperfectly, and “mathematicals” (geometrical lines and figures) less imperfectly still. But the eternal, unchangeable <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/form-philosophy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">forms</a>—and only they—exhibit being perfectly.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>5. Some metaphysicians have affirmed, and others have denied, that existence is a property or attribute of everything that exists. Kant, the most famous critic of the thesis, identified it as the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/fallacy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">fallacy</a> on which the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/ontological-argument" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">ontological argument</a> for the existence of God depends. Deniers of the thesis have maintained that “existence” statements are only apparently about the things that are their grammatical subjects and so cannot be understood as attributing a certain property to those things. <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Gottlob-Frege" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Gottlob Frege</a> (1848–1925), for example, held that the statement “Horses exist” really means “The number of objects that fall under the concept horse is not zero.”</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD40]--><span class="marker PREMOD40 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">A theory of existence may be identified with some combination of the theses discussed above. It should be noted, however, that some combinations are inconsistent, or at least apparently so. For example, anyone who accepts Frege’s account of existence seems to be committed to the theses that existence is a trivial concept, that there is no distinction to be made between being and existence, that <em>existence</em> means the same thing in all its applications, and that existence is not something that one thing can exhibit more perfectly or in some higher degree than another.</p><!--[MOD40]--><span class="marker MOD40 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344389"> <h2 class="h2">Universals and particulars</h2> <!--[PREMOD41]--><span class="marker PREMOD41 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Many philosophers have believed that, in addition to particular things, there are “general” things of which particular things are instances or examples or cases. They have believed, for example, that, in addition to particular horses, the world contains the species <em>Equus caballus</em>, a general thing of which every horse is an instance (and of which only horses are instances). The Latin word for such general things is <em>universalia</em> (singular <em>universale</em>).</p><!--[MOD41]--><span class="marker MOD41 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD42]--><span class="marker PREMOD42 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The complex history of the Latin term may be briefly summarized as follows.</p><!--[MOD42]--><span class="marker MOD42 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD43]--><span class="marker PREMOD43 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Plato had used the (ancient Greek) adverbial phrase <em>kath’ holou</em> (“as a whole”) in statements such as, “I am interested not in this or that case of virtue but in virtue taken <em>kath’ holou</em>.” His student <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Aristotle" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Aristotle</a> (384–322 <span class="text-smallcaps">bce</span>) used the word <em>katholou</em>, a noun coined from the adverbial phrase, as a name for those things that could be <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="predicated" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/predicated" data-type="MW">predicated</a> or said of a thing—thus, “being virtuous” and “being white” are <em>katholou</em>. Later philosophers writing in Latin, seeking a noun corresponding to <em>katholou</em>, settled on <em>universale</em> and <em>universalia</em>, the neuter singular and neuter plural forms, respectively, of the adjective <em>universalis</em> (“universal”). They chose <em>universalis</em> for that purpose because it is derived from another adjective, <em>universus</em>, which means “taken as a whole.”</p><!--[MOD43]--><span class="marker MOD43 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD44]--><span class="marker PREMOD44 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">A strikingly high proportion of the writings of <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="medieval" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/medieval" data-type="MW">medieval</a> philosophers is directed at disputes about the nature of <em>universalia</em> (“universals”) and the nature of their relation to the “particulars” that are their instances. The medieval interest in universals is at least partly to be explained by the respect for philosophical authority characteristic of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/event/Middle-Ages" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Middle Ages</a> and by the fact that the two greatest authorities of antiquity, Plato and Aristotle, had disagreed about such matters.</p><!--[MOD44]--><span class="marker MOD44 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD45]--><span class="marker PREMOD45 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">According to Plato, when the same general word (e.g., <em>horse, spear, river</em>) applies to different particulars (or to the same particular at different times), it does so by virtue of the fact that those things bear a common relation to a certain form or idea—a supersensible, eternal, and changeless being. If, for example, the word <em>horse</em> applies to each of two particulars, it is only because both of them fall under or “participate” in the form Horse. (And if <em>horse</em> applies to Bucephalus on both Sunday and Monday, it is only because Bucephalus participates in Horse on both Sunday and Monday.) If the application to particular things of general terms like <em>horse</em> were not in some way guided by an understanding of their associated forms (Plato contended), the fact that speakers apply the word to each of two particular things would be a mere accident and would not reflect any common nature among the things so designated—as is the case with the application of the name <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Heraclitus" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Heraclitus</a> to each of a dozen or so ancient Greeks. It seems to be an indisputable consequence of Plato’s theory of forms that the existence of any form does not require that there be a particular thing that participates in it. If, for example, horses were to become extinct, the form Horse, being eternal and changeless, would continue to exist.</p><!--[MOD45]--><span class="marker MOD45 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD46]--><span class="marker PREMOD46 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Aristotle agreed with Plato on one important point: that when a general term is applied to many particular things, its application is “guided” by knowledge of something that those things have in common. Aristotle denied, however, that what (for example) all horses have in common is participation in a changeless, eternal, independently existing form. In his view, what all horses have in common is something that inheres in each horse—in each of the multiplicity of particular horses.</p><!--[MOD46]--><span class="marker MOD46 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD47]--><span class="marker PREMOD47 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Four schools of thought emerged from the medieval disputes about universals and their relation to particulars.</p><!--[MOD47]--><span class="marker MOD47 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Platonists, or <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="Platonic" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Platonic" data-type="MW">Platonic</a> realists, affirmed the existence of <em>universalia ante rem</em> (or <em>ante res</em>): universals “before the thing” (or “before things”). That is, they held that general things—the things that account for the fact that a general word applies to many particulars—exist independently of those particulars. According to medieval Platonic <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/realism-philosophy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">realism</a>, before God created any horses, the species horse, or the attribute “being a horse” (or both), already existed. Some Platonists, concerned to avoid the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="implication" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/implication" data-type="MW">implication</a> that anything might exist independently of God, identified <em>universalia ante rem</em> with ideas in the mind of God.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. Aristotelians, or Aristotelian realists, affirmed the existence of universals but contended that they were <em>universalia in re</em> (or <em>in rebus</em>): universals “in the thing” (or “in things”). According to Aristotelians, universals exist only as <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="constituents" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/constituents" data-type="MW">constituents</a> of particulars. The word <em>horse</em> applies to two things by virtue of their having a certain universal as a common constituent—the species horse or the attribute “being a horse” (or both). If God had not been pleased to create horses, the Aristotelians maintained, neither the species horse nor the attribute “being a horse” would have existed.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Nominalists denied the existence of both <em>universalia ante rem</em> and <em>universalia in re</em>. Reality, they maintained, consists entirely of particulars. The word <em>horse</em>, then, does not refer to a universal, whether before or in things, but simply denotes all horses. Some nominalists did not so much deny the existence of universals as identify them with the general terms whose application Platonists and Aristotelians had <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="invoked" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/invoked" data-type="MW">invoked</a> “universals” to explain. (The term <em>nominalism</em> is derived from the Latin word <em>nomina</em>, “names.”) A universal, such nominalists contended, is a mere “puff of sound” (<em>flatus vocis</em>).</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>4. Finally, conceptualists held that universals are mental entities, confined to individual human minds. Thus, any person’s use of the general term <em>horse</em> is governed by a concept that exists only in that person’s mind. Another person’s use of the word is governed by a numerically distinct concept in that other person’s mind—and those two concepts may well differ in content, with the consequence that the two speakers apply <em>horse</em> to different things. There is no question of a speaker’s associating the “wrong” concept with the word <em>horse</em>—except in so far as that concept leads the speaker to apply the word to objects different from those to which the majority of fellow speakers apply it.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD52]--><span class="marker PREMOD52 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The schools described above are, to a very large extent, abstractions. In practice, it is often difficult to place a given philosopher in any one of them to the complete exclusion of the others. (It is often particularly hard to decide whether a given philosopher should be called a nominalist or a conceptualist.) As a very general rule, it can be said that philosophers writing in Latin in late <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="antiquity" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/antiquity" data-type="EB">antiquity</a> tended to be Platonic realists, that philosophers of the high Middle Ages tended to be Aristotelian realists, and that philosophers of the late Middle Ages tended to be nominalists.</p><!--[MOD52]--><span class="marker MOD52 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD53]--><span class="marker PREMOD53 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Theories of universals received relatively little attention from philosophers of the Renaissance and modern periods (roughly from the 16th through the 19th century). That was particularly true of the empirically minded British philosophers of the 18th century, who generally adopted an uncritical <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/nominalism" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">nominalism</a> and who tended to regard any attempt at serious discussion of the nature of universals as so much <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Scholasticism" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Scholastic</a> quibbling.</p><!--[MOD53]--><span class="marker MOD53 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD54]--><span class="marker PREMOD54 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">In the 20th century there was a remarkable resurgence of interest in theories of universals. There were, on the one hand, a significant number of philosophers who defended the thesis that an appeal to Aristotelian universals explains various features of the world (e.g., that a green book and a green apple have something in common). And there was, on the other hand, a revival of Platonic realism, in large part a consequence of the realism about mathematical objects advocated by <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Bertrand-Russell" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Bertrand Russell</a> (1872–1970) and the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-logic" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">philosophy of logic</a> of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Willard-Van-Orman-Quine" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">W.V.O. Quine</a> (1908–2000), particularly his views on <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/quantification" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">quantification</a> and “ontological commitment.”</p><!--[MOD54]--><span class="marker MOD54 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344390"> <h2 class="h2">Causation</h2> <!--[PREMOD55]--><span class="marker PREMOD55 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The word <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/causation" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true"><em>causation</em></a> applies to relations of two distinct kinds. To resolve the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="ambiguity" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/ambiguity" data-type="MW">ambiguity</a>, it is necessary to distinguish between the idea of “the” causal relation and the idea of “a” causal relation. The terms of “the” causal relation are causes and effects, and causes and effects are, by definition, events or facts or states of affairs. That relation—the relation between cause and effect—is expressed by phrases such as <em>caused, was the cause of, was one of the causes of, led to,</em> and <em>had as an effect.</em> Its converse is expressed by phrases such as <em>was caused by, was an effect of, was due to, occurred because, was the result of,</em> and <em>was a consequence of.</em> To affirm that an event or fact or state of affairs (a cause) bears the causal relation to another such item (an effect) is to imply that the former in some sense explains the latter.</p><!--[MOD55]--><span class="marker MOD55 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD56]--><span class="marker PREMOD56 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">It will be convenient to have an <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="unambiguous" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/unambiguous" data-type="EB">unambiguous</a> name for the causal relation. In the remainder of the present section, this relation will be called the cause-effect relation.</p><!--[MOD56]--><span class="marker MOD56 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD57]--><span class="marker PREMOD57 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">By contrast, the terms of “a” causal relation—there are many of them—are substances (<em>see below</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344391" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Substance</a>) or <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/concrete-philosophy" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">concrete</a> objects or particular things or entities. That is, they are items such as fingers and billiard balls and souls—as opposed to items such as a finger’s pressing a button, a billiard ball’s striking another billiard ball, and a soul’s performing an act of will. Such causal relations are expressed by words and phrases such as <em>pushed, pulled, touched, bent, struck, cut, kissed, killed, bored a hole in, exerted a force on, acted on, affected,</em> and <em>brought into existence.</em></p><!--[MOD57]--><span class="marker MOD57 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD58]--><span class="marker PREMOD58 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Again, it will be convenient to have an unambiguous name for such causal relations. In the remainder of the present section, they will be called agent-patient relations, a term that indicates that they are relations that a thing bears to another thing by virtue of the way in which the former acts on the latter.</p><!--[MOD58]--><span class="marker MOD58 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD59]--><span class="marker PREMOD59 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The philosophical topic of causation <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="comprises" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/comprises" data-type="EB">comprises</a> the cause-effect relation, the many agent-patient relations, and the relation between the two, for the cause-effect relation and the many agent-patient relations are intimately connected. Agent-patient relations, for example, often figure in descriptions of causes, as in the statement, “She died as the result of being struck by a car.” That statement asserts that the event or state of affairs “(her) being struck by a car” bore the cause-effect relation to the event or state of affairs “(her having) died,” and the former item is described in terms of an agent-patient relation (“being struck”) between a certain vehicle and a certain human being.</p><!--[MOD59]--><span class="marker MOD59 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD60]--><span class="marker PREMOD60 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="128314" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-050-404073CE/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/128314"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-050-404073CE/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-050-404073CE/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg?w=300" alt="David Hume" data-width="1364" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/08/131908-050-404073CE/David-Hume-oil-canvas-Allan-Ramsay-Scottish-1766.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/128314">David Hume</a><span>David Hume, oil on canvas by Allan Ramsay, 1766; in the Scottish National Portrait Gallery, Edinburgh.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">In Greek and medieval philosophical texts, the Greek words <em>aition</em> (or <em>aitia</em>) and the Latin word <em>causa</em>—each of which is usually translated as “cause”—almost always refer to agent-patient relations of one kind or another. Present-day philosophical <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="treatments" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/treatments" data-type="EB">treatments</a> of causation, however, are devoted almost entirely to the cause-effect relation, reflecting the enormously influential work of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/event/Scottish-Enlightenment" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Scottish Enlightenment</a> philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/David-Hume" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">David Hume</a> (1711–76) but also in part the influence on philosophy of Newtonian and post-Newtonian science. Although not all philosophers (even within the Anglophone philosophical tradition) accept Hume’s account of causation, most would agree with Hume on one important point: the central topic in a philosophical study of causation should be the cause-effect relation. Most philosophers would, in fact, suppose that agent-patient relations are not an important part of the topic of causation and that they should in any case be understood or analyzed in terms of the cause-effect relation. For example, they would for the most part <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="subscribe" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/subscribe" data-type="EB">subscribe</a> to the following thesis:</p><!--[MOD60]--><span class="marker MOD60 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>A satisfactory philosophical analysis of the statement “The Earth exerts a gravitational force on the Moon” should take the form of a statement to the effect that some (specified) event or fact or state of affairs that involves the Earth is the cause of a certain effect—to wit, some (specified) event or fact or state of affairs that involves the Moon.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD62]--><span class="marker PREMOD62 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">According to Hume, to say that event A is the cause of event B is to say that events that are very much like A have always been followed by events that are very much like B—that events very much like A have been “constantly conjoined” in human experience with events very much like B. For example, to say that a billiard ball’s being struck by another billiard ball was the cause of the movement of the former ball is to say that the first ball was stuck by the second and that events very much like that striking have always been followed by events very much like the first ball’s movement. Hume thus rejects the idea of a “necessary connection” between cause and effect: the concept of one ball’s coming into contact with another does not contain or imply the concept of the latter’s moving. The idea of such a connection, he contends, arises from the experience of constant conjunction, which creates a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="disposition" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/disposition" data-type="MW">disposition</a> in the human mind to expect an event B after having observed an event A, given that events very much like A have always been followed by events very much like B.</p><!--[MOD62]--><span class="marker MOD62 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD63]--><span class="marker PREMOD63 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Many later philosophers in the Anglophone philosophical tradition have accepted some refinement of Hume’s theory of causation. (And refinements are obviously necessary: if people always hear a church bell ringing immediately after the chiming of their own clocks, it does not follow that the clocks’ chiming is the cause of the church bell’s ringing.) Contemporary Humean theories are usually framed in terms of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/law-of-nature" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">laws of nature</a>. One such formulation, for example, is:</p><!--[MOD63]--><span class="marker MOD63 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>An event A is the cause of an event B if and only if there is some property F of A and some property G of B such that ‘an event with property F is always followed by an event with property G’ is a <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/law-of-nature" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">law of nature</a> or a logical consequence of such a law.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD65]--><span class="marker PREMOD65 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">They maintain, moreover, that laws of nature are merely the most general of the observed regularities in nature and are in no sense <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/necessity-philosophy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">necessary</a> truths.</p><!--[MOD65]--><span class="marker MOD65 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD66]--><span class="marker PREMOD66 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="110184" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-050-79127006/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/110184"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-050-79127006/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-050-79127006/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg?w=300" alt="Immanuel Kant" data-width="1066" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/74/102174-050-79127006/Immanuel-Kant-print-London-1812.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/110184">Immanuel Kant</a><span>Immanuel Kant, print published in London, 1812.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">Although he admired Hume’s analysis of causation, Kant maintained that what he called “causality” (<em>Kausalität</em>) did indeed include the idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect. In the <em><a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Immanuel-Kant/Period-of-the-three-Critiques#ref27122" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Critique of Pure Reason</a></em>, he argued that causality is an a priori category, or pure concept of the understanding. Because it does not derive from experience, it is possible to have the concept of causation without directly perceiving the necessity that is <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="inherent" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/inherent" data-type="MW">inherent</a> in it. Because the categories apply only to experience, however, they cannot be used to establish the existence or nature of anything that is not itself an object of possible experience (e.g., God, freedom, and <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/immortality" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">immortality</a>). Thus, the traditional <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/cosmological-argument" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">cosmological argument</a>, which attempts to prove the existence of a “first cause” of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/universe" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">universe</a> (i.e., God), is invalid, according to Kant.</p><!--[MOD66]--><span class="marker MOD66 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD67]--><span class="marker PREMOD67 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Few present-day philosophers would agree with Kant that causation is an a priori category. Indeed, most <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="contemporary" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/contemporary" data-type="EB">contemporary</a> philosophers of causation either accept some version of Hume’s account or at least share his assumption that the central topic in the philosophy of causation should be the analysis of the cause-effect relation. There is, however, one important exception to that generalization. Some 20th-century writers on <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/free-will" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">free will</a> revived the medieval idea of substantial causation, which can be understood as a hybrid of an agent-patient relation and the cause-effect relation. Those philosophers contended that it is possible for an event (or fact or state of affairs) to have been caused not by an earlier event (or fact or state of affairs) but by a substance. It may be, they argued, that, when people raise their arms, the people themselves—and not any event or fact or state of affairs—are the cause of their arms rising. Indeed, they maintained, that is what a free act consists of: an act caused by its agent (a substance) and not caused by any prior event or fact or state of affairs.</p><!--[MOD67]--><span class="marker MOD67 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344391"> <h2 class="h2">Substance</h2> <!--[PREMOD68]--><span class="marker PREMOD68 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="122142" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-050-F6C9719C/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/122142"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-050-F6C9719C/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-050-F6C9719C/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg?w=300" alt="Benedict de Spinoza" data-width="1366" data-height="1600" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/58/126158-050-F6C9719C/Benedict-de-Spinoza-oil-painting-Wolfenbuttel-Germany-1665.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/122142">Benedict de Spinoza</a><span>Benedict de Spinoza, oil painting, c. 1665; in the Herzog August Bibliothek, Wolfenbüttel, Germany.</span><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">Although substance is one of the most important ideas in <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="metaphysics" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/metaphysics" data-type="EB">metaphysics</a>, philosophers disagree about which entities are substances. For Aristotle, the first philosopher to make substance a central concept in his thought, the best examples of substances (among tangible, visible things) were living organisms. For <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Benedict-de-Spinoza" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Benedict de Spinoza</a> (1632–77), who also gave the concept a central place in his philosophy, there was only one substance, which constitutes the whole of reality. Spinoza held that living organisms are mere “finite modes” of the one (infinite) substance.</p><!--[MOD68]--><span class="marker MOD68 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD69]--><span class="marker PREMOD69 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">If one assumes that Aristotle and Spinoza employed the same concept of substance (Aristotle holding that the best examples of substances were biological organisms, and Spinoza taking the view that the only substance was the whole of reality), then the concept must be very abstract indeed. A suitably broad concept might be set out as follows: a substance is a <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344389" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">particular</a> that exists “in its own right”—i.e., a particular thing that could exist independently of other particular things (although it may in fact have been brought into existence by the action of other particular things). But that attempt at explaining the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="concept" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/concept" data-type="EB">concept</a> of substance raises the following questions: What is the concept of substance opposed to? What sort of particular is not a substance? In other words, what particulars might be said to be incapable of existing independently of other particulars?</p><!--[MOD69]--><span class="marker MOD69 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD70]--><span class="marker PREMOD70 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Such questions are best answered by giving examples. Some things (if they exist at all) are present only “in” other things: e.g., a smile, a wrinkle, a surface, a hole, a reflection, or a shadow. There is a clear sense in which such items, even if one is willing to grant real existence to them, do not exist in their own right. They might be called “ontological parasites,” things incapable of existing apart from the things that are their “hosts.” (A wrinkle in a carpet cannot exist apart from the carpet; a hole in a piece of cheese cannot exist apart from the cheese.) If one supposed that a carpet could, in <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="metaphysical" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/metaphysical" data-type="EB">metaphysical</a> theory if not in physical fact, exist apart from all other things (other than its own parts), one would be supposing that the carpet was a substance, but no one would suppose that a wrinkle in that carpet could be a substance. The carpet may or may not exist in its own right, but the wrinkle certainly does not. (Spinoza would have insisted that the carpet did not exist in its own right—that only the one substance, which constitutes the whole of reality, exists in its own right, the carpet being as much an ontological parasite as the wrinkle.)</p><!--[MOD70]--><span class="marker MOD70 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD71]--><span class="marker PREMOD71 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Aristotle had called things that exist in their own right <em>prōtai ousiai</em> (“primary beings”; singular <em>prōtē ousia</em>), which make up the most important of his ontological categories. Several features define <em>prōtai ousiai</em>: they are subjects of predication that cannot themselves be predicated of things (they are not universals); things exist “in” them, but they do not exist “in” things (they are not “accidents,” like <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Socrates" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Socrates’</a> wisdom or his <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="ironic" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/ironic" data-type="MW">ironic</a> smile); and they have determinate identities (essences). The last feature could be expressed in modern terms as follows: if a <em>prōtē ousia</em> <em>x</em> exists at a certain time and a <em>prōtē ousia</em> <em>y</em> exists at some other time, there is a determinate answer to the question of whether <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> are one and the same thing, or numerically identical; and the question of whether a given <em>prōtē ousia</em> would exist in some specific set of counterfactual circumstances must likewise have a determinate answer. It is difficult to suppose that smiles or wrinkles or holes have this sort of determinate identity. To ask whether the smile that Socrates smiled today is the same as the smile that he smiled yesterday can be understood only as a question about descriptive identity, the relation between two distinct things whereby they are exactly like each other in every respect (<em>see below</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344392" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Identity</a>).</p><!--[MOD71]--><span class="marker MOD71 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD72]--><span class="marker PREMOD72 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Aristotle used (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em> not only as a count noun but also as a mass term. (He generally wrote <em>ousia</em> without qualification when he believed that the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="context" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/context" data-type="MW">context</a> would make it clear that he meant <em>prōtē ousia</em>.) For example, he asked not only questions like “Is Socrates a (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em>?” and “What is a (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em>?” but also questions like “What is the (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em> of Socrates?” and “What is (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em>?” In the count-noun sense of the term, Aristotle identified at least some (<em>prōtai</em>) <em>ousiai</em> with <em>ta hupokeimena</em> (“underlying things”; singular <em>to hupokeimenon</em>). Socrates, for example, is a <em>to hupokeimenon</em> in that he “lies under” the <em>in rebus</em> (Latin: “in the things”) universals under which he falls and the accidents that inhere in him. <em>To hupokeimenon</em> has an approximate Latin equivalent in <em>substantia</em>, “that which stands under.” Owing both to the close association of (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em> and <em>to hupokeimenon</em> in Aristotle’s philosophy and to the absence of a suitable Latin equivalent of <em>ousia</em> (the closest <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="analogue" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/analogue" data-type="MW">analogue</a>, <em>essentia</em>, a made-up Latin word formed in imitation of <em>ousia</em>, was used for another purpose), <em>substantia</em> became the customary Latin translation of the count noun (<em>prōtē</em>) <em>ousia</em>. A <em>substantia</em> or substance is thus a particular that is capable of “standing on its own.” A substance may indeed depend on the action of other substances for its existence: it may have been brought into existence by the prior operations of other substances, and it may depend on the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="concurrent" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/concurrent" data-type="MW">concurrent</a> operations of other substances to continue in existence. But it does not depend on other things for its existence in the manner in which a wrinkle or a hole in a carpet depends on the carpet for its existence.</p><!--[MOD72]--><span class="marker MOD72 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD73]--><span class="marker PREMOD73 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Although there is no universally accepted and precise definition of “substance” (alternatively, one might say that substance is not a very clear concept), most philosophers would agree that certain kinds of things are not substances. For example, most philosophers who are willing to use the word at all would <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="deny" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/deny" data-type="EB">deny</a> that any of the following (if they exist) are substances:</p><!--[MOD73]--><span class="marker MOD73 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Universals and other abstract objects. (It should be noted that Aristotle criticized Plato for supposing that <em>prōtai ousiai</em> are <em>ante res</em>, Latin for “before things,” universals.)</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. Events, processes, or changes. Some philosophers have held that there are substances that are nontemporal, or outside time. But substances that are temporal are said to last or endure or to exist at various times. Events or processes, on the other hand, are said to happen, occur, or take place.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Stuffs, such as flesh, iron, or butter. Although a common meaning of “substance” is stuff or matter, Aristotle criticized earlier philosophers (specifically, the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Western-philosophy/Ancient-Greek-and-Roman-philosophy#ref8566" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">pre-Socratic</a> cosmologists) for supposing that a <em>prōtē ousia</em> could be a stuff such as water, air, fire, or earth.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD77]--><span class="marker PREMOD77 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The question of whether there are substances continues to be one of the central problems of metaphysics. Several closely related questions are the following. How, precisely, should the concept of substance be understood? Among the sorts of things that human beings frequently encounter, which (if any) are substances? If there are substances, how many of them are there? (For example, is there only one, as Spinoza contended, or are there many, as his fellow rationalists Descartes and Leibniz supposed?) What kinds of substances are there? (For example, are there immaterial substances, eternal substances, or necessarily existent substances?)</p><!--[MOD77]--><span class="marker MOD77 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344392"> <h2 class="h2">Identity</h2> <!--[PREMOD78]--><span class="marker PREMOD78 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">When one says, for example, that the room in which Hegel lectured was identical with the room in which Schopenhauer lectured, there are two quite different things that one might mean. The first is that the two philosophers lectured in rooms that were in different places but were of the same <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="dimensions" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/dimensions" data-type="EB">dimensions</a> and were in every other respect exact duplicates of each other. (It is in this sense of “identical” that <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/dizygotic-twin" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">monozygotic twins</a> are said to be identical.) The second is that Hegel and Schopenhauer lectured in one and the same room (though presumably at different hours). Identity of the former sort is called descriptive identity, and identity of the latter sort is called numerical identity—“numerical” because, if <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> are identical in that sense, there is only one of them; some one thing is both <em>x</em> and <em>y</em>. Although the concept of descriptive identity has received a considerable amount of attention from philosophers, numerical identity is the more important of the two <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="concepts" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/concepts" data-type="EB">concepts</a> for metaphysics.</p><!--[MOD78]--><span class="marker MOD78 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD79]--><span class="marker PREMOD79 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The logical properties of numerical identity have been precisely codified by logicians, who express it by the sign “=.” The sign has been borrowed from mathematics, but (the logicians insist) without any change of meaning. According to logicians, a mathematical equation—a formula that consists of two expressions surrounding the symbol “=”—is simply a statement of numerical identity. The equation 7 + 5 = 2 × 6, for example, differs from the statement “<a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Mark-Twain" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Mark Twain</a> is (numerically) identical with Samuel Clemens” in its subject matter—the latter is about a person (the person who was called both “Mark Twain” and “Samuel Clemens”) and the former about a number (the number that is <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="designated" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/designated" data-type="EB">designated</a> by both “7 + 5” and “2 × 6”)—but not in its logical structure. The properties of “=” are, according to the standard <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/formal-logic" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">formal logic</a> of identity, exactly those expressed by two axioms: <em>x</em> = <em>x</em>, which says that any object <em>x</em> is identical with <em>x</em>—that is, with itself—and (<em>x</em> = <em>y</em>) ⊃ (F<em>x</em> ≡ F<em>y</em>), which says that if an object <em>x</em> and an object <em>y</em> are identical, then something F is true of <em>x</em> if and only if F is also true of <em>y</em>. Thus, because Mark Twain and Samuel Clemens were identical, Mark Twain was fond of buttered toast if and only if Samuel Clemens was fond of buttered toast. The latter axiom has been called both the principle of the indiscernibility of identicals and Leibniz’s law (<em>see</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/identity-of-indiscernibles" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">identity of indiscernibles</a>). It can be intuitively stated as follows: if <em>x</em> is identical with <em>y</em>, whatever is true of <em>x</em> is true of <em>y</em> and whatever is true of <em>y</em> is true of <em>x</em>.</p><!--[MOD79]--><span class="marker MOD79 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD80]--><span class="marker PREMOD80 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">There are apparent exceptions to Leibniz’s law. Consider, for example, the following argument:</p><!--[MOD80]--><span class="marker MOD80 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Mark Twain chose that name as a nom de plume.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. Mark Twain was identical with Samuel Clemens.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Therefore, Samuel Clemens chose that name as a nom de plume.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD84]--><span class="marker PREMOD84 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">It might appear that Leibniz’s law incorrectly implies that the preceding <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="inference" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/inference" data-type="MW">inference</a> is valid. Almost all philosophers agree, however, that the argument is not a counterexample to Leibinz’s law, because the phrase “chose that name as a nom de plume” does not really express something that can be true of or false of someone.</p><!--[MOD84]--><span class="marker MOD84 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD85]--><span class="marker PREMOD85 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The following argument, often attributed to Descartes, is widely regarded by philosophers as a similarly <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="fallacious" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/fallacious" data-type="MW">fallacious</a> attempt to apply Leibinz’s law.</p><!--[MOD85]--><span class="marker MOD85 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. The following is true of my body: I can imagine that it does not really exist, though it seems to me that it does exist. (For example, I can imagine that I have been dreaming my whole life through and that the world of material things that I seem to perceive around me is no more than a figment of my long dream.)</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. The following is not true of me: I can imagine that I do not really exist, though it seems to me that I do exist.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Therefore, I am not identical with my body.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD89]--><span class="marker PREMOD89 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The argument is a “contrapositive” application of Leibniz’s law. The law implies that if a person and that person’s body are identical, then what is true of either is true of the other; it follows that if something is true of a person’s body that is not true of that person, then the person and the person’s body are not identical.</p><!--[MOD89]--><span class="marker MOD89 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD90]--><span class="marker PREMOD90 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The standard criticism of this argument is that the phrase “I can imagine that <em>x</em> does not exist, though it seems to me that it does exist” does not express something that can be true or false of a thing. A moment’s reflection shows that if those words did in fact express something that could be true or false of a thing, then no first-person identity statement more informative than “I am I” or “I am myself” could be true. If, for example, <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Lee-Harvey-Oswald" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Lee Harvey Oswald</a> had been brought to trial for having murdered <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/John-F-Kennedy" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">John F. Kennedy</a>, he could have established his innocence by arguing as follows:</p><!--[MOD90]--><span class="marker MOD90 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. The following is true of the murderer of John F. Kennedy: I can imagine that he does not exist, though it seems to me that he does exist.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. The following is not true of me: I can imagine that I do not really exist, though it seems to me that I do exist.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>3. Therefore, I am not identical with the murderer of John F. Kennedy.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD94]--><span class="marker PREMOD94 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">It is easy to prove that the two <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="axioms" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/axioms" data-type="EB">axioms</a> of identity (Lebiniz’s law and “Everything is identical with itself”) logically imply that identity has the following features: it is symmetrical (if Mark Twain is identical with Samuel Clemens, then Samuel Clemens is identical with Mark Twain); it is transitive (if Byzantium is identical with Constantinople and if Constantinople is identical with Istanbul, then Byzantium is identical with Istanbul); and it conforms to “Euclid’s law,” or the principle that identicals may be substituted for identicals (if angle A is twice as large as angle B and if angle C is identical with angle A, then angle C is twice as large as angle B). Indeed, Leibniz’s law is nothing more than a somewhat more careful statement of Euclid’s law.</p><!--[MOD94]--><span class="marker MOD94 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD95]--><span class="marker PREMOD95 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The principle of the indiscernibility of identicals must be carefully distinguished from its contrapositive, the principle of the identity of indiscernibles. The latter principle may be stated as follows: “If whatever is true of <em>x</em> is also true of <em>y</em> and if whatever is true of <em>y</em> is also true of <em>x</em>, then <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> are identical.” (Alternatively: “If <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> have all of the same properties, then <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> are identical.”) The fact that the principle of the indiscernibility of identicals is also called Leibniz’s law and the fact that the principle of the identity of indiscernibles plays a central role in Leibniz’s metaphysics have no doubt encouraged confusion between the two principles.</p><!--[MOD95]--><span class="marker MOD95 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD96]--><span class="marker PREMOD96 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The principle of the identity of indiscernibles is a trivial truth if there are “individual essences”—that is, properties of a thing that consist of its being that particular thing and no other thing (e.g., Plato would have the property of being Plato, the Taj Mahal would have the property of being the Taj Mahal, and so on). If there are individual essences, then the principle would imply that each thing is identical with itself and with no other thing. However, many philosophers doubt that such individual essences really exist, and almost all philosophers who have expressed an opinion on the question believe that, individual essences apart, the principle of the identity of indiscernibles is not a necessary truth; that is, it is possible to imagine without contradiction a universe in which the principle would be false. (According to the American philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Max-Black" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Max Black</a> [1909–88], for example, the principle would not hold in a “symmetrical universe” consisting of two mathematically perfect balls of the same size and substance floating in an <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="infinite" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/infinite" data-type="MW">infinite</a> void. If there are no individual essences, then the two balls would have exactly the same properties, including relational properties, though they would not be the same ball.)</p><!--[MOD96]--><span class="marker MOD96 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD97]--><span class="marker PREMOD97 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Some of the most important philosophical debates about identity have to do with identity across time, particularly the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/personal-identity" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">identity of persons</a> across time. The thesis that there is such a thing as identity across time is simply the view that one and the same entity may exist at more than one time—or, equivalently, that it is possible for a thing existing at one time and a thing existing at another time to be numerically identical. It would seem that almost everyone unreflectively believes that there are real cases of identity across time. Any history of physics, for example, will state that a certain person, <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Albert-Einstein" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Albert Einstein</a>, formulated the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/relativity/Special-relativity#ref252878" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">special theory of relativity</a> in 1905 and formulated the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/relativity/General-relativity#ref252889" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">general theory of relativity</a> in 1915. If that statement is true, then the person who formulated the special theory of relativity in 1905 was identical with the person who formulated the general theory of relativity in 1915. Nevertheless, the commonsense assumption that Einstein in 1905 was identical with Einstein in 1915 is at least apparently inconsistent with Leibniz’s law, since Einstein in 1905 and Einstein in 1915 did not have all of the same properties (e.g., Einstein in 1905 was 26 years old, whereas Einstein in 1915 was 36 years old).</p><!--[MOD97]--><span class="marker MOD97 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD98]--><span class="marker PREMOD98 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Philosophers have proposed various solutions to the preceding problem. Some would say that Einstein existed at different times in virtue of having “<a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="temporal" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/temporal" data-type="EB">temporal</a> parts” that individually occupied various points in, or segments of, time. One temporal part of Einstein, some would say, formulated the special theory, and another part formulated the general theory. Other philosophers would say that there is no problem to be solved by an appeal to temporal parts: the problem, the apparent violation of Leibniz’s law, is due to a failure properly to understand what is asserted by sentences such as “The person who formulated the special theory of relativity in 1905 was 26 years old.” What that sentence “really” says, they contend, is that the person who formulated the special theory of relativity in 1905 was 26 years old when he formulated the special theory of relativity. When that fact is appreciated, they go on to say, the apparent violation of Leibniz’s law vanishes, for the person who formulated the general theory of relativity in 1915 also had that property—that is, the property of being 26 years old when he formulated the special theory of relativity.</p><!--[MOD98]--><span class="marker MOD98 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD99]--><span class="marker PREMOD99 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">One factor that makes problems of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/personal-identity" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">personal identity</a> particularly difficult is the tension between the psychological and physical aspects of common <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="intuitions" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/intuitions" data-type="MW">intuitions</a> about what it is for the same person to exist at different times. If, for example, a person’s memory is entirely obliterated by some procedure that leaves the person’s body unaffected, does that person still exist? (This is a case of physical <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="continuity" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/continuity" data-type="MW">continuity</a> and psychological discontinuity.) Or, if a science-fictional “transporter” or “teleportation machine” should become a reality, would the human being who emerged from teleportation by such a machine be the same person as the (psychologically identical) human being who had entered the machine a spilt second earlier? (A case of psychological continuity and physical discontinuity.) Possible solutions vary with the concept of identity one employs and the metaphysics of parts and wholes one appeals to, but any plausible solution must be consistent with Leibniz’s law.</p><!--[MOD99]--><span class="marker MOD99 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD100]--><span class="marker PREMOD100 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Many of the most challenging problems about identity across time are raised by cases that involve a thing’s changing its parts. An ancient example, known as “the ship of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Theseus-Greek-hero" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Theseus</a>,” may be posed as follows. A new ship, made entirely of wooden planks, is named the <em>Ariadne</em>. The <em>Ariadne</em> puts to sea, and, while it is sailing, the planks of which it is constructed are replaced (gradually and one at a time) by new planks, each replacement plank being descriptively identical with the plank it replaces. The original planks are taken ashore and stored in Piraeus (the port of ancient Athens). After all of the planks have been replaced, the ship constructed entirely of the replacement planks is still sailing in the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/place/Aegean-Sea" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">Aegean Sea</a> (the Aegean ship). The old planks are then assembled in a <a href="https://www.britannica.com/technology/dry-dock" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">dry dock</a> in Piraeus to form a new ship (the Piraean ship). The planks that <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="constitute" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/constitute" data-type="MW">constitute</a> the Piraean ship stand in the same spatial relations to one another as they did when they first <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="constituted" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/constituted" data-type="MW">constituted</a> the <em>Ariadne</em>. The Aegean ship and the Piraean ship are obviously not the same ship, since they are in different places at the same time. But which (if either) is the <em>Ariadne</em>? The problem of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/ship-of-Theseus-philosophy" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">ship of Theseus</a> is the problem of finding the right answer to that question.</p><!--[MOD100]--><span class="marker MOD100 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD101]--><span class="marker PREMOD101 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">One might argue that the Aegean ship is the <em>Ariadne</em>, because a ship does not cease to exist when one of its <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="constituent" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/constituent" data-type="MW">constituent</a> planks is replaced; hence, during the gradual replacement of its planks, there was no point at which the <em>Ariadne</em> ceased to be the ship it originally was. But one could also argue that the Piraean ship is the <em>Ariadne</em>, because the Piraean ship and the <em>Ariadne</em> (at the first moment of its existence) are composed of exactly the same planks arranged in exactly the same way.</p><!--[MOD101]--><span class="marker MOD101 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD102]--><span class="marker PREMOD102 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Again, possible solutions to the problem will vary depending on concept of identity and on the metaphysics of parts and wholes, but any solution must be consistent with Leibniz’s law.</p><!--[MOD102]--><span class="marker MOD102 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD103]--><span class="marker PREMOD103 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The concept of numerical identity has also figured essentially in philosophical <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="critiques" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/critiques" data-type="MW">critiques</a> of various <span id="ref361784"></span><a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Christianity" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Christian</a> theological doctrines, particularly those of the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Trinity-Christianity" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Trinity</a>, the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Incarnation-Jesus-Christ" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Incarnation</a>, and the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/Eucharist" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Eucharist</a>. Many philosophers have held that, for example, the doctrine of the Trinity (the unity in one Godhead of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit) violates the principle of the transitivity of identity, since it implies, for example, that the Father and the Son are identical with God but not identical with each other.</p><!--[MOD103]--><span class="marker MOD103 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD104]--><span class="marker PREMOD104 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The English Roman Catholic philosopher Peter Geach (1916–2013) proposed a radical solution to the theological problem regarding the transitivity of identity. According to Geach, there is no such thing as numerical identity; there are, instead, many relations of the form “is the same F as,” where “F” is a sortal term <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="designating" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/designating" data-type="EB">designating</a> a kind of thing (e.g., “human being,” “animal,” “living organism”; “plank,” “ship,” “material object”; and so on). Geach maintained that no rule of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/logic" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">logic</a> licenses an inference from “<em>x</em> is the same F as <em>y</em>” to “<em>x</em> is the same G as <em>y</em>,” if “F” and “G” represent logically independent sortal terms. Accordingly, as far as logic is concerned, it is perfectly possible for there to be entities <em>x</em> and <em>y</em> such that: (1) <em>x</em> is the same F as <em>y</em>, but (2) <em>x</em> is not the same G as <em>y</em>. Geach’s theory would thus permit one to reformulate the Trinitarian <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="implication" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/implication" data-type="EB">implication</a> above as follows: (1) the Father is the same God as the Son (i.e., the Father and the Son are both God), but (2) the Father is not the same person as the Son.</p><!--[MOD104]--><span class="marker MOD104 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD105]--><span class="marker PREMOD105 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Geach’s theory is characterized as the view that “identity is relative to a sortal term,” or simply as the “theory of relative identity.” It has attracted some attention among philosophers and logicians, but not as much as it might have had it been clear that the theory had some application outside Christian <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/theology" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">theology</a>, a matter of some dispute. It does seem, however, that the theory of relative identity might be applied to some of the problems of identity over time discussed above. In the case of the ship of Theseus, for example, one might propose the following: (1) since there is no such relation as numerical identity, the question of whether the <em>Ariadne</em> is the Aegean ship or the Piraean ship is meaningless; (2) the <em>Ariadne</em>, the Aegean ship, and the Piraean ship are all ships and all material things; (3) the <em>Ariadne</em> and the Aegean ship are the same ship but not the same material thing; and (4) the <em>Ariadne</em> and the Piraean ship are the same material thing but not the same ship.</p><!--[MOD105]--><span class="marker MOD105 mod-inline"></span> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344393"> <h2 class="h2">Persistence through time</h2> <!--[PREMOD106]--><span class="marker PREMOD106 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">A thing is said to <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="persist" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/persist" data-type="EB">persist</a> through <span id="ref361783"></span><a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/time" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true"> time</a>, or simply to persist, if it exists at more than one moment of time. Because persistence implies that the same object exists at more than one moment of time, persistence is often referred to as identity through (or across) time. Some philosophical problems concerning persistence or identity through time have more to do with identity than with time, and others have more to do with time than with identity. Problems of the former kind were discussed in the preceding section (<em>see above</em> <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/metaphysics/Problems-in-metaphysics#ref344392" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Identity</a>); the present section concerns problems of the latter kind.</p><!--[MOD106]--><span class="marker MOD106 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD107]--><span class="marker PREMOD107 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Theories or accounts of persistence may be divided into two broad types: those based on the view that time is very much like <span id="ref361782"></span><a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/space-physics-and-metaphysics" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">space</a> and those based on the view that time and space are fundamentally different.</p><!--[MOD107]--><span class="marker MOD107 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD108]--><span class="marker PREMOD108 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Metaphysicians who belong to the former school regard identity across time as closely <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="analogous" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/analogous" data-type="MW">analogous</a> to “identity across space.” The latter kind of identity is exemplified by the identity of a river that is encountered in one place with a river that is encountered in another place. What is it to say that two bridges span the same river despite the fact that they are distant from each other? The obvious answer is that the river consists of many parts or segments, and one of the bridges spans one of the segments that compose the river and the other bridge spans another of those segments. Accordingly, philosophers who regard identity across time as closely analogous to identity across space adopt a similar analysis—appealing to temporally distinct parts or segments—when analyzing problems of the former kind.</p><!--[MOD108]--><span class="marker MOD108 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD109]--><span class="marker PREMOD109 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">For example, suppose that a certain cat existed at the moment of its <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="conception" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/conception" data-type="EB">conception</a> in 1832, at the moment of its death in 1844, at all moments in between those two moments, and at no other moments. Just as a river (considered at any moment of its existence) is composed of many spatial river-segments, a cat (considered over the whole course of its life) is composed of many temporal cat-segments, or “temporal parts” of the cat. There are, for example, the 1837-part of the cat and the 1840-part of the cat, each with a temporal extension of one year, and the June 11, 1835-part of the cat, with a temporal extension of 24 hours. To say that the kitten that Princess Victoria stroked in 1832 was identical with the dying cat that <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Victoria-queen-of-United-Kingdom" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Queen Victoria</a> stroked in 1844 is to say that Princess Victoria stroked a small, kittenish temporal part of a cat in 1832, that Queen Victoria stroked a large, <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="moribund" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/moribund" data-type="MW">moribund</a> temporal part of a cat in 1844, and that those two temporal cat-parts were parts of the same temporal whole. That temporal whole, or whole cat, is a thing extended in time, a “space-time worm” whose endpoints are a moment in 1832 and a moment in 1844.</p><!--[MOD109]--><span class="marker MOD109 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD110]--><span class="marker PREMOD110 mod-inline"></span><div class="assemblies"><div class="w-100"><figure class="md-assembly m-0 mb-md-0 card card-borderless print-false" data-assembly-id="99991" data-asm-type="image"><div class="md-assembly-wrapper card-media" data-type="image"><a href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg" class="gtm-assembly-link position-relative d-flex align-items-center justify-content-center media-overlay-link card-media" data-href="/media/1/377923/99991"><picture><source media="(min-width: 680px)" srcset="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg?w=300"><img src="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg?w=300" alt="David Kellogg Lewis" data-width="363" data-height="450" loading="eager"></picture><button class="magnifying-glass btn btn-circle position-absolute shadow btn-white top-10 right-10" aria-label="Zoom in"><em class="material-icons link-blue" data-icon="zoom_in"></em></button></a></div><figcaption class="card-body"><div class="md-assembly-caption text-muted font-14 font-serif line-clamp"><span><a class="gtm-assembly-link md-assembly-title font-weight-bold d-inline font-sans-serif mr-5 media-overlay-link" href="https://cdn.britannica.com/18/99818-004-4F6B91F4/David-Kellogg-Lewis.jpg" data-href="/media/1/377923/99991">David Kellogg Lewis</a><button class="js-more-btn d-none btn btn-unstyled font-12 bg-white js-content" aria-label="Toggle more/less fact data"><span class="link-blue">(more)</span></button></span></div></figcaption></figure></div></div><p class="topic-paragraph">Thus, to persist through time is simply to have temporal parts that exist at different times. The American philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/David-Kellogg-Lewis" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">David Lewis</a> (1941–2001) proposed that an object that exists at more than one time by being composed of a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="plurality" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/plurality" data-type="EB">plurality</a> of temporal parts should be said to “perdure,” and he called the thesis that there are persisting things—and that they persist by perduring—the perdurance theory, or “perdurantism.” Most Anglophone philosophers (whether or not they agree with Lewis) have adopted those terms.</p><!--[MOD110]--><span class="marker MOD110 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD111]--><span class="marker PREMOD111 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The perdurance theory is not the only theory that treats time as being very much like space, though it is the most widely accepted theory of that kind. A rival theory maintains that, although the perdurance theory presents a correct account of what persistence would consist of if there were such a thing, there in fact is no such thing as persistence. There exists nothing in addition to the momentary things that the perdurance theory wrongly describes as temporal parts of persisting or temporally extended things. The members of the temporal sequences of momentary things that, according to the perdurance theory, compose temporally extended things are connected by a relation of causal continuity called “gen-identity,” but that fact does not imply the existence of temporally extended wholes that have them as parts.</p><!--[MOD111]--><span class="marker MOD111 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD112]--><span class="marker PREMOD112 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Because the gen-identity theory denies that persistence exists, it is not, strictly speaking, a theory of persistence. It is perhaps better described as a theory of the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="illusion" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/illusion" data-type="MW">illusion</a> of persistence, an illusion that is due to a faulty (and frequently unconscious) inference whereby observers who encounter a temporal succession of momentary things related by gen-identity mistakenly conclude that those momentary things are parts of a temporally extended whole.</p><!--[MOD112]--><span class="marker MOD112 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD113]--><span class="marker PREMOD113 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Metaphysicians who accept the reality of persistence but regard time as fundamentally different from space deny that persisting things are, as the perdurantists hold, composed of temporal parts. The idea of a temporal part, they argue, depends essentially on a belief in the fundamental similarity of time and space, for the idea of a temporal part makes sense only if things are extended in time, and things can be supposed to be extended in time only if time is sufficiently like space that the idea of extension—an idea derived from the experience of physical distances between points in space—can, by a species of analogical generalization, be applied to the intervals between moments of time.</p><!--[MOD113]--><span class="marker MOD113 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD114]--><span class="marker PREMOD114 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">If such opponents of the perdurance theory are challenged to produce their own account of persistence, they will typically respond that no such account is possible. And that is because a demand for an account of persistence can be understood only as a demand for an analysis of the concept of persistence in terms of simpler or more fundamental or better-understood concepts—and, according to them, no concept is simpler or more fundamental or better understood than the concept of an object’s existing at more than one time. (They will not <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="concede" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/concede" data-type="EB">concede</a> that the perdurantists have provided such an analysis, because the perdurantists’ proposed analysis is intelligible only if time and space are sufficiently alike that the concept of extension, spatial in origin, can be generalized to apply to intervals of time.) Lewis called their position “endurantism,” a term that he intended to be used in opposition to “perdurantism,” and most metaphysicians have accepted the pair of terms as the standard way of referring to the two theories.</p><!--[MOD114]--><span class="marker MOD114 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD115]--><span class="marker PREMOD115 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">It must be said, however, that many perdurantists would object to any reference to endurantism as a “theory.” Perdurantists commonly charge that, although endurantism is obviously a thesis about persistence, it is not a theory of persistence. They <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="contend" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/contend" data-type="EB">contend</a> that the entire content of endurantism is contained in the statement “persisting objects are not composed of temporal parts,” which is equivalent to the statement that a certain theory of persistence—their theory, perdurantism—is wrong. And, they point out, a statement that a particular theory of something is wrong, even if true, is not itself a theory of that something. (For example, the statement, “<a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Isaac-Newton" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Newton</a>’s theory of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/gravity-physics" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">gravity</a> is wrong,” even if true, is not a theory of gravity.)</p><!--[MOD115]--><span class="marker MOD115 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD116]--><span class="marker PREMOD116 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">In response to such objections, some endurantists have granted that endurantism is not a theory of persistence (because there could not be any theory of persistence) but have insisted that it is no worse for not being one. Endurantism, they hold, is a correct philosophical thesis about persistence, and that is all that it needs to be.</p><!--[MOD116]--><span class="marker MOD116 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD117]--><span class="marker PREMOD117 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Other endurantists, however, have replied to the perdurantists by <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="denying" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/denying" data-type="EB">denying</a> that the entire content of endurantism is contained in the statement that perdurantism is wrong. Endurantism, they hold, is also the positive thesis—in fact, the “theory”—that, if a persisting object exists at a certain moment, then the whole of that object, rather than merely a temporal part of it, exists at that moment (alternatively, the object is wholly present at that moment). They therefore maintain that the persistence of an object through time consists in its being wholly existent or present at different moments. And that thesis, they contend, is no less a theory of persistence than perdurantism is.</p><!--[MOD117]--><span class="marker MOD117 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD118]--><span class="marker PREMOD118 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Many perdurantists (and some endurantists), however, have expressed <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="uncertainty" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/uncertainty" data-type="EB">uncertainty</a> about how such a theory should be understood. What, they wonder, does a sentence like “Victoria’s cat was wholly present at every moment of its existence” mean? They point out that, if the sentence means only that Victoria’s cat was a persisting thing but not a temporally extended thing composed of briefer temporal parts, then the following two theses are two statements of the same thesis, two ways of saying the same thing.</p><!--[MOD118]--><span class="marker MOD118 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. The persistence of an object through time consists in its being wholly existent or present at different moments.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. The persistence of an object through time does not consist in its being composed of temporal parts that exist at different moments.</p> </div></li></ul> <!--[PREMOD121]--><span class="marker PREMOD121 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">And, if that is so, the former statement is a negative thesis in an <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="affirmative" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/affirmative" data-type="MW">affirmative</a> disguise—a thesis about what persistence is not that has been made to look like a statement about what persistence is by verbal sleight-of-hand.</p><!--[MOD121]--><span class="marker MOD121 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD122]--><span class="marker PREMOD122 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">If such challenges to the concept of an object’s being wholly existent or present at a moment cannot be met, then perdurantism and endurantism should not be regarded as rival accounts of persistence. It should rather be conceded that perdurantism is the sole theory of persistence (which is not to say that it is a correct theory, of course). Endurantism, moreover, should be described as a metaphysical thesis or position—and not as a metaphysical theory—that comprises the following two merely negative theses:</p><!--[MOD122]--><span class="marker MOD122 mod-inline"></span> <ul class="list-none "><li><div> <p>1. Perdurantism is to be rejected, owing to the fact that it implies that persisting objects have temporal parts when, in fact, there are no such things as temporal parts. The concept of a temporal part is a product of a false picture of time, a picture that represents time as being much more like space than it really is.</p> </div></li><li><div> <p>2. There exist no concepts in terms of which a theory of persistence could be stated, for any such concept would have to be simpler or more fundamental or better understood than the concept of a persisting thing (the concept of a thing that exists at more than one moment of time), and no concept is simpler or more fundamental or better understood than the concept of a persisting thing.</p> </div></li></ul> </section> <section data-level="2" id="ref344394"> <h2 class="h2">Modality</h2> <!--[PREMOD125]--><span class="marker PREMOD125 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The two statements “Tokyo is the capital of Japan” and “There is no largest prime number” are both true, but they differ in their relation to <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/truth-philosophy-and-logic" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">truth</a> in the following important respect: whereas the former statement could have been false, the latter statement could not have been false. That is to say, the former statement is contingently true, or “contingent,” and the latter statement is necessarily true, or “necessary.”</p><!--[MOD125]--><span class="marker MOD125 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD126]--><span class="marker PREMOD126 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The two statements “Yokohama is the capital of Japan” and “There is no smallest prime number” are both false. The former, however, could have been true, but the latter could not have been true. That is to say, the former statement is contingently false (it is false but possibly true, or “possible”), and the latter statement is necessarily false, or “impossible.”</p><!--[MOD126]--><span class="marker MOD126 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD127]--><span class="marker PREMOD127 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The concepts expressed by the words within quotation marks in the preceding two paragraphs are called “modal” concepts. The term <em>modal</em> originated in a medieval theory of necessity and <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="contingency" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/contingency" data-type="MW">contingency</a> according to which statements can be true in various “modes.” For example, the mode in which “Tokyo is the capital of Japan” is true is contingency, while the mode in which “There is no largest prime number” is true is necessity. Although philosophers no longer speak of contingency and necessity as modes of truth, the term <em>modal</em>—meaning “pertaining to possibility, impossibility, necessity, and contingency”—has been retained. Similarly, the noun <em>modality</em> is simply an abbreviated way of referring to any or all of the categories of possibility, impossibility, necessity, and contingency.</p><!--[MOD127]--><span class="marker MOD127 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD128]--><span class="marker PREMOD128 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph"><a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="Modality" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Modality" data-type="MW">Modality</a> that has to do with the truth or falsity of propositions is sometimes called “alethic” modality (from the Greek <em>alētheia</em>, “truth”). Alethic modality is contrasted with “epistemic” modality (from the Greek <em>epistēmē</em>, “knowledge”), which is the kind of modality expressed by phrases such as “For all anyone knows…,” “No one knows whether…,” “It must be the case that…,” “It couldn’t be the case that…,” and so on. A relatively oblique expression of epistemic modality, for example, is the statement “It is possible that this number is prime,” as uttered by a mathematician. Although the number in question is either prime or not prime, and the number could not have been not prime if it is prime or prime if it is not prime, the mathematician’s statement means only that no known mathematical <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="consideration" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/consideration" data-type="EB">consideration</a> lends any support either to the thesis that the number is prime or to the thesis that that the number is not prime. (The notion of epistemic modality will not be further discussed in the present section; it is mentioned here only as a means of distinguishing it from, and clarifying, the notion of alethic modality.)</p><!--[MOD128]--><span class="marker MOD128 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD129]--><span class="marker PREMOD129 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">In addition to the modal adjectives “contingent,” “possible,” “necessary,” and “impossible,” the vocabulary of modality includes the modal operators “it is possible that” and “it is necessary that.” The following two schemas display the relation between the operators and their corresponding adjectives (the term “<em>p</em>” represents any proposition): (1) it is possible that <em>p</em> if and only if <em>p</em> is possible, and (2) it is necessary that <em>p</em> if and only <em>p</em> is necessary.</p><!--[MOD129]--><span class="marker MOD129 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD130]--><span class="marker PREMOD130 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">All <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="modal" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/modal" data-type="EB">modal</a> terms can be given definitions that involve only one “basic” or “primitive” modal term, whether <em>possible</em> or <em>necessary</em>. For example, one might start with <em>necessary</em> and define <em>possible</em> as follows: “It is possible that <em>p</em> if and only if it is not the case that it is necessary that it is not the case that <em>p</em>.” Or one might start with <em>possible</em> and define <em>necessary</em> as follows: “It is necessary that <em>p</em> if and only if it is not the case that it is possible that it is not the case that <em>p</em>.” Both <em>contingent</em> and <em>impossible</em>, moreover, can easily be defined in terms of either <em>possible</em> or <em>necessary</em>.</p><!--[MOD130]--><span class="marker MOD130 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD131]--><span class="marker PREMOD131 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Beginning in the second half of the 20th century, it became increasingly common for philosophers concerned with modality to approach the topic via the Leibnizian concept of <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/possible-world" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">possible worlds</a>. (A possible world is usually explained intuitively as a total way that things might have been or might be, or as a possible history and future of the world. The actual world is itself a possible world, the one that represents or constitutes the way things are.) Thus, a proposition is possibly true if it is true in some (at least one) possible world, necessarily true if it is true in all possible worlds, impossible if it is true in no possible world, and contingently true if it is true in the actual world but false in some possible world. Philosophers who employ the concept of possible worlds generally think of them as <a href="https://www.britannica.com/science/abstraction" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">abstract</a> objects (an important exception was David Lewis), about which there are objective, mind-independent truths.</p><!--[MOD131]--><span class="marker MOD131 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD132]--><span class="marker PREMOD132 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">For example, assuming that <a href="https://www.britannica.com/art/science-fiction/Time-travel#ref235731" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">time travel</a> has been precisely defined, either there exist possible worlds in which time travel occurs or there exist no such worlds. If such worlds exist, time travel is “metaphysically” possible; if no such worlds exist, time travel is metaphysically impossible. If time travel is metaphysically possible but occurs only in worlds in which the <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/law-of-nature" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">laws of nature</a> are different from those of the actual world, then time travel, despite its metaphysical possibility, is physically impossible. If time travel is physically possible (existing in some worlds in which the laws of nature are the actual laws) but occurs only in worlds in which technology is far in advance of the technology of the present actual world, then time travel, despite its physical possibility, is (at present) technologically or practically impossible. Physical and technological impossibility are examples of what are called “restricted” or “relative” modalities—those that are relative to one or more specifiable factors (e.g., the laws of nature or a certain level of technology). The term “metaphysical modality” is a common way of referring to absolutely unrestricted modality, or modality that is not relativized to any particular factor.</p><!--[MOD132]--><span class="marker MOD132 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD133]--><span class="marker PREMOD133 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The modality that is discussed above (excepting a brief mention of epistemic modality) is the modality of propositions, or the modality of truth and falsity. The modality of propositions is sometimes thought of as being only a species of the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="genus" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/genus" data-type="EB">genus</a> modality, the other species being the modality of things. The two species are customarily designated by the medieval Latin terms <em>de dicto</em> (from <em>dictum</em>, a thing that has been said) and <em>de re</em> (from <em>res</em>, thing). The modality discussed above is therefore modality de dicto.</p><!--[MOD133]--><span class="marker MOD133 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD134]--><span class="marker PREMOD134 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Whereas modality <em>de dicto</em> has to do with the relation of propositions to their truth-values (i.e., to truth and falsity), modality <em>de re</em> has to do with the relation of things to their properties (i.e., features, qualities, attributes, or characteristics). The basic concepts of modality <em>de re</em> are the accidental and the essential (or necessary) possession of properties: a thing has a property accidentally if it has that property in the actual world but lacks it in some possible world in which it exists, and a thing has a property essentially or necessarily if it has it in every possible world in which it exists. For example, <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Michelangelo" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Michelangelo</a>’s <em>David</em> is now in Florence, but it has that feature (the feature of being in Florence) only accidentally, since it could at some point have been moved to some other city without <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off eb" data-term="ceasing" href="https://www.britannica.com/dictionary/ceasing" data-type="EB">ceasing</a> to exist: there are possible worlds in which the <em>David</em> is in Rome or Beijing. But it seems evident that the <em>David</em> could not have existed without being a material thing—there is no possible world in which the <em>David</em> is immaterial—and that it therefore it has the property being a material thing essentially, or necessarily.</p><!--[MOD134]--><span class="marker MOD134 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD135]--><span class="marker PREMOD135 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">In the 20 years following <a href="https://www.britannica.com/event/World-War-II" class="md-crosslink autoxref " data-show-preview="true">World War II</a>, owing principally to arguments of the American philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Willard-Van-Orman-Quine" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">W.V.O. Quine</a>, a “deflationary” theory of modality was ascendant. According to that theory, necessity is nothing more than <a href="https://www.britannica.com/topic/analytic-proposition" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">analyticity</a>, or the quality of a proposition whereby it is true by virtue of the meanings of the terms that are used to express it (a standard example is “All bachelors are unmarried”).</p><!--[MOD135]--><span class="marker MOD135 mod-inline"></span> <!--[PREMOD136]--><span class="marker PREMOD136 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">The deflationary theory was held to entail that necessity <em>de re</em> is an incoherent concept. The argument for that conclusion was supposed to have been established by Quine’s famous “mathematical cyclist” argument, an <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="adaptation" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/adaptation" data-type="MW">adaptation</a> of which is the following:</p><!--[MOD136]--><span class="marker MOD136 mod-inline"></span> <blockquote> <p>Suppose that the proposition “All cyclists are bipedal” is analytic. The proposition “All mathematicians are bipedal” is obviously not analytic. Given that necessity is a matter of analyticity, it follows that necessity <em>de re</em>, if it is a <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="coherent" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/coherent" data-type="MW">coherent</a> notion, is a matter of analyticity. Therefore, all cyclists are necessarily bipedal, and all mathematicians are not necessarily bipedal (i.e., no mathematicians are necessarily bipedal). It follows that the American cyclist and mathematician Julia Robinson (1919–85) was necessarily bipedal (because she was a cyclist) and not necessarily bipedal (because she was a mathematician)—a contradiction. Because the notion of necessity <em>de re</em> thus implies a contradiction (given the deflationary theory), it is incoherent.</p> </blockquote> <!--[PREMOD138]--><span class="marker PREMOD138 mod-inline"></span><p class="topic-paragraph">Since about 1970, however, most philosophers in the <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="analytical" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/analytical" data-type="MW">analytical</a> tradition have been convinced by the work of the American philosopher <a href="https://www.britannica.com/biography/Saul-Kripke" class="md-crosslink " data-show-preview="true">Saul Kripke</a> and others that the mathematical-cyclist argument fails. Those philosophers point out that there obviously exist possible worlds in which Robinson is not bipedal or at least ceased to be bipedal at some very early age. She might, for example, have lost a leg in an accident when she was an infant. She is, therefore, accidentally bipedal. It may be plausibly <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="stipulated" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/stipulated" data-type="MW">stipulated</a> that she is bipedal in every possible world in which she is a cyclist. But she is a cyclist only accidentally, since there are possible worlds in which she is not a cyclist. Accordingly, the proposition “All cyclists are bipedal,” even if it is assumed to be necessary, does not imply that all cyclists are necessarily bipedal, understood as an <a class="md-dictionary-link md-dictionary-tt-off mw" data-term="attribution" href="https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/attribution" data-type="MW">attribution</a> of necessity <em>de re</em>. It seems, in fact, that no cyclist is necessarily bipedal: all cyclists (all people who are actually cyclists) exist in possible worlds in which they do not have two legs.</p><!--[MOD138]--><span class="marker MOD138 mod-inline"></span> <span class="md-signature"><a href="/contributor/Peter-van-Inwagen/6110">Peter van Inwagen</a></span> </section> </section><!--[END-OF-CONTENT]--><span class="marker end-of-content"></span><!--[AFTER-ARTICLE]--><span class="marker after-article"></span></div> <div id="chatbot-root"></div> </div> </div> </div> <div class="ai-dialog-placeholder"></div> </div> </div> <aside class="col-md-da-320"></aside> </div> </div> </div> </div> </article> </div> </div> </div> </div> </main> <div id="md-footer"></div> <noscript><iframe src="//www.googletagmanager.com/ns.html?id=GTM-5W6NC8" height="0" width="0" style="display:none;visibility:hidden"></iframe></noscript> <script type="text/javascript" id="_informizely_script_tag"> var IzWidget = IzWidget || {}; (function (d) { var scriptElement = d.createElement('script'); scriptElement.type = 'text/javascript'; scriptElement.async = true; scriptElement.src = "https://insitez.blob.core.windows.net/site/f780f33e-a610-4ac2-af81-3eb184037547.js"; var node = d.getElementById('_informizely_script_tag'); node.parentNode.insertBefore(scriptElement, node); } )(document); </script> <!-- Ortto ebmwprod capture code --> <script> window.ap3c = window.ap3c || {}; var ap3c = window.ap3c; ap3c.cmd = ap3c.cmd || []; ap3c.cmd.push(function() { ap3c.init('ZO4siT4cLwnykPnzZWJtd3Byb2Q', 'https://engage.email.britannica.com/'); ap3c.track({v: 0}); }); ap3c.activity = function(act) { ap3c.act = (ap3c.act || []); ap3c.act.push(act); }; var s, t; s = document.createElement('script'); s.type = 'text/javascript'; s.src = "https://engage.email.britannica.com/app.js"; t = document.getElementsByTagName('script')[0]; t.parentNode.insertBefore(s, t); </script> <script class="marketing-page-info" type="application/json"> {"pageType":"Topic","templateName":"DESKTOP","pageNumber":2,"pagesTotal":4,"pageId":377923,"pageLength":12558,"initialLoad":true,"lastPageOfScroll":false} </script> <script class="marketing-content-info" type="application/json"> [] </script> <script src="https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/js/libs/jquery-3.5.0.min.js?v=3.133.9"></script> <script type="text/javascript" data-type="Init Mendel Code Splitting"> (function() { $.ajax({ dataType: 'script', cache: true, url: 'https://cdn.britannica.com/mendel-resources/3-133/dist/topic-page.js?v=3.133.9' }); })(); </script> <script class="analytics-metadata" type="application/json"> {"leg":"D","adLeg":"C","userType":"ANONYMOUS","pageType":"Topic","pageSubtype":null,"articleTemplateType":"PAGINATED","gisted":false,"pageNumber":2,"hasSummarizeButton":false,"hasAskButton":true} </script> <script type="text/javascript"> EBStat={accountId:-1,hostnameOverride:'webstats.eb.com',domain:'www.britannica.com', json:''}; </script> <script type="text/javascript"> ( function() { $.ajax( { dataType: 'script', cache: true, url: '//www.britannica.com/webstats/mendelstats.js?v=1' } ) .done( function() { try {writeStat(null,EBStat);} catch(err){} } ); })(); </script> <div id="bc-fixed-dialogue"></div> </body> </html>