CINXE.COM

The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

<HTML> <HEAD> <TITLE>The Principles of Friesian Philosophy</TITLE> </HEAD> <BODY bgcolor="#ffffff" rgb="#000000" text="#000000" link="#ff0000" vlink="#0000ff"> <center><img src="images/key.gif"></center> <H1 ALIGN="center">The Principles<br>of Friesian Philosophy</H1> <p><center><img src="images/key.gif"></center> <P><blockquote><font size=+1>Then let us again examine, Euthyphro, whether that is a sound statement [&#x03b5;&#x1f30; &#x03ba;&#x03b1;&#x03bb;&#x1ff6;&#x03c2; &#x03bb;&#x03ad;&#x03b3;&#x03b5;&#x03c4;&#x03b1;&#x03b9; -- if said <a href="domain.htm#beauty">truly</a>], or do we let it pass, and if one of us, or someone else, merely says that something is so, do we accept that it is so? Or should we examine [&#x1f22; &#x03c3;&#x03ba;&#x03b5;&#x03c0;&#x03c4;&#x03ad;&#x03bf;&#x03bd;] what the speaker means? [&#x03c4;&#x03af; &#x03bb;&#x03ad;&#x03b3;&#x03b5;&#x03b9; &#x1f41; &#x03bb;&#x03ad;&#x03b3;&#x03c9;&#x03bd;; -- what the speaker says?]</font> <P><B>Socrates</B>, <a href="euthyph.htm#examine"><I>Euthryphro</I> 9e</a> [G.M.A. Grube translation, Plato, <I>Five Dialogues, Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo</I>, Hackett Publishing Company, 1981, p. 14] <hr> <P><font size=+1>On the other hand, excellence of every kind is always only an exception, one case in millions; therefore, <img src="images/arthur.jpg" align=right>if it has shown itself in a lasting work, this subsequently exists in isolation, after it has outlived the rancour of its contemporaries. It is preserved like a <font color=red>meteorite</font>, sprung <font color=red>from another order of things</font>, from that which prevails here. <P>Hingegen das Treffliche jeder Art immer nur eine Ausnahme, ein Fall aus Millionen ist, daher auch, wenn es sich in einem dauernden Werke kund gegeben, dieses nachher, nachdem es den Groll seiner Zeitgenossen &uuml;berlebt hat, isolirt dasteht, aufbewahrt wird, gleich einem <font color=red>Meteorstein</font>, <font color=red>aus einer andern Ordnung der Dinge</font>, als die hier herrschende ist, entsprungen.</font> <P><a href="arthur.htm"><B>Arthur Schopenhauer</B></a>, <I>Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung</I>, Band 1, &sect;59 [Reclam, 1987, p.457], <I>The World as Will and Representation</I>, Volume I [Dover Publications, 1966, E.F.J. Payne translation, p.324], translation modified, color added. <hr> <P><font size=+1>The professor of philosophy who forgets that philosophy is about <a href="wisdom.htm"><I>wisdom</I></a> may still be a real lover of knowledge, may still be a great creative scholar, and may even still be a very good person, but he will not really be <I>a philosopher</I>. When he speaks, especially on moral, practical, or political matters, his words may represent nothing but the most dangerous folly, without the Socratic perspective and drive to correct it. All too often, <I>brilliant fools</I> seem to be the stock-in-trade of academia and the intelligentsia -- remembering George Orwell saying that some things are so absurd, that only an intellectual would believe them.</font> <P><font size=+1>&#x03a4;&#x03b7;&#x03bb;&#x03b5;&#x03c0;&#x03b1;&#x03c4;&#x03b7;&#x03c4;&#x03b9;&#x03ba;&#x03cc;&#x03c2;</font> (<a href="ross/ross-9.htm#farwalk">Telepateticus</a>)</blockquote> <p><center><img src="images/bar.gif"></center> <P>This page is intended as a brief description of ideas and principles characteristic of the Friesian and other modifications of Kantian philosophy editorially recommended in the <I>Proceedings of the Friesian School, Fourth Series</I>. More detailed explanations will be found elsewhere at the site. For brevity, familiarity with certain philosophical issues and theories is often presupposed, so these descriptions may not be as accessible as the essays listed on the Home Page under <a href="./#contents">"Topics and Essays on the Site"</a>. <ul> <p><li><H2>Epistemology</H2> <P>Kantian epistemology is foundationalist and rationalistic in a qualified sense. <a href="kant.htm">Kant</a> allowed that there were synthetic <I>a priori</I> propositions in mathematics, grounded in "pure intuition," in metaphysics, grounded on the Principle of the Possibility of Experience, and in morality, grounded on Pure Reason acting as the Moral Law. <a href="fries.htm">Fries</a> and <a href="nelson.htm">Nelson</a> modified Kantian epistemology, first, by clarifying that synthetic <I>a priori</I> propositions are not <I>proven</I> by Kantian "Deduction," second, by clearly distinguishing immediate knowledge, which is the ground of synthetic propositions, from mediate knowledge, which is expressed in propositional form and may be <I>justified</I> by immediate knowledge, and, third, by distinguishing intuitive from <I>non-intuitive</I> immediate knowledge. <P>On Friesian principles, the common argument against the existence of immediate knowledge, that it would require us to claim that certain synthetic propositions are infallible and incorrigible, which today no longer seems credible, fails. Immediate knowledge as the <I>ground</I> of synthetic propositions may in some sense be infallible and incorrigible, but the expression of any propositions themselves, as items of knowledge, is mediate. Mediate knowledge presupposes many things that are not part of immediate knowledge, e.g. the meanings of words in natural languages, or items of implicit knowledge. Thus, mediate knowledge is always fallible and corrigible. This allows Friesian epistemology to accommodate a <I>hermeneutic dimension</I> of interpretation and reinterpretation, with the common sense limitation that the interpretations of synthetic propositions must be <I>recognized</I> as grounded by immediate knowledge in order to be <I>true</I>. <P>If synthetic <I>a priori</I> propositions are not grounded in intuitive immediate knowledge, where the ground need merely be shown ("demonstrated" in Friesian terminology) for fallible and corrigible justification, then they can only be grounded in <a href="immedi-1.htm">non-intuitive immediate knowledge</a>. Such a ground cannot be "shown." The difference between discovery and justification then becomes significant. Discovery is handled by Nelson's theory of <a href="foundatn.htm">Socratic Method</a>. But while Nelson's theory of Socratic Method as "abstraction" is intuitionistic and inadequate, the theory is easily reformulated in terms of <a href="popper.htm">Popper's</a> theory of <I>falsification</I>, which winnows out inconsistent items. Popper's theory of scientific method, where theories are imaginatively generated, may thus be coupled with the Socratic injunction, "Say what you believe," to recover what Kant called the "quid facti" of rational knowledge. <P>The theory of non-intuitive immediate knowledge frees the Kantian epistemology of synthetic <I>a priori</I> propositions from the narrow confines of the Principle of the Possibility of Experience and from vague appeals to Pure Reason as the ground of the Moral Law. Instead, independent axiomatic systems become possible for varieties of non-empirical knowledge, not just metaphysics but also the multiple value systems of morality, aesthetics, and religion. However, a difference remains, as follows in the next section, between phenomena and things-in-themselves which, among other things, limits mathematical knowledge from application beyond phenomenal reality. <P>Friesian epistemology is basically an internalist theory of knowledge. "Externalist" theories, based on some external relationship, like causality, to account for knowledge, are rejected on the principle that the difference between knowledge and opinion can only be distinguished on the basis of some internal <B>evidence</B>. No external relationship is available for internal <B>examination</B> as evidence for knowledge. On the other hand, Kantian metaphysics, as follows, holds that external relationships <B>are</B> internal in that the objects of experience are phenomenal contents of consciousness. Thus Friesian epistemology in fact can subsume externalist considerations within itself. (However, note well, the treatment in <a href="undecd-1.htm">"Ontological Undecidability"</a> and elsewhere shifts the meaning of "external" and "internal" so that Kant-Friesian epistemology is <I>neither</I> externalist nor internalist.) <P>Similarly, Friesian epistemology combines both the coherence and the correspondence theories of truth: the <B>coherence</B> of mediate with immediate knowledge, but then the <B>correspondence</B> of mediate knowledge to the empirically real phenomenal objects that are present in immediate knowledge. This avoids traditional criticisms of coherence, that it allows for no relationship to reality, since reality is in immediate knowledge, and traditional criticisms of correspondence, that it posits a ground of truth inaccessible to knowledge, since phenomenal objects are within consciousness. <P>Thus, on several fronts, Kant-Friesian epistemology passes over into metaphysical considerations. <p><li><H2>Metaphysics</H2> <P>Kantian metaphysics recognizes the difference between phenomena and things-in-themselves. <a href="arthur.htm">Schopenhauer</a> thought this was the most important thing about Kant's thought. Nevertheless, Kant's phenomenalism is often mistaken for some kind of subjectivist, conceptualist, or psychologistic theory. <a href="system.htm"><img src="images/metaphy2.gif" border=0 align=right></a>The key point about it all, therefore, is that Kant's phenomenalism is a theory of <I><B>empirical realism</B></I>, according to which we are <I>directly acquainted</I> with real external objects in space and time. Unlike the familiar case of Descartes, what Kant would call "transcendental realism," we are not merely acquainted with the internal and private contents of our minds, though phenomena are <I>that too</I> (see <a href="undecd-1.htm">"Ontological Undecidability"</a>). Instead, we are justified in our common sense attitude towards the world, whereby Dr. Johnson refuted Bishop Berkeley by kicking the table. This implies that the real objects of experience are present in our perception, and Kant's theory is that this is correct. Such a theory precludes the Cartesian threats of scepticism or solipsism. <P>On the other hand, there are <I>things-in-themselves</I>. Traditionally these could be interpreted as the "real" objects ("transcendental realism"), turning Kant's "transcendental idealism" into just another version of Descartes or Berkeley, raising the same classic Cartesian problems of knowledge, mind and body, etc. Schopenhauer realized the most clearly the mistake involved in that interpretation; and, since he didn't think that plurality applied beyond perceptual objects, he always carefully referred to the "thing-in-itself" rather than to "things-in-themselves." The scruple is not necessary, but it does reveal that things-in-themselves are not a parallel order of objects over and above phenomenal objects. They are just the <I>transcendent aspect</I> of those very same phenomenal objects. They are indeed things (as we see them) "in themselves." <P>The transcendence of phenomenal objects encompasses different things: <P><ol><li><B>The <I>existence</I> of objects in so far as they are separate and independent from our existence.</B> This is conformable to Heidegger's distinction between <I>beings</I> (<B>&oacute;nta</B> in Greek, "being things"), which are individual and phenomenal, and <I>Being</I> (<B>e&icirc;nai</B> in Greek, "to be"), which is general and "hidden," although manifest in the <B>&oacute;nta</B>. It is also conformable to <a href="spinoza.htm">Spinoza's</a> distinction between <I>natura naturata,</I> "nature natured," manifest individual things, and <I>natura naturans,</I> "nature naturing," the hidden power that <I>manifests</I> the individual things. What seemed like no more than an epistemological or psychological theory in Descartes is thus a metaphysical distinction instead, although this needed clarifying after the way Kant formulated it. <P><li><B>Aspects of reality that may be <I>unconditioned</I>.</B> In phenomenal reality everything conditions everything else, which requires a deterministic and naturalistic view of the world. Unconditioned objects, like Kant's "Ideas" of God (an absolutely unconditioned object, as Spinoza had defined God), freedom (an unconditioned cause), and immortality (the unconditioned self as the soul), simply cannot exist in such a deterministic and naturalistic universe. However, such issues also intrude into science, since cosmology deals with the unconditioned object of the universe as a whole. Thus, whether space and time are finite or infinite, and whether the universe has a beginning or an end, trouble the consideration of people who are far above metaphysical speculations about God or the soul. Kant treated all such problems together, as transcending phenomenal reality: No unconditioned object is an object of a possible experience. Significantly, the <a href="buddhism.htm#basic">Buddhist philosophical doctrines</a> of "dependent origination" and "relative existence" parallel the Kantian theory of conditioned, phenomenal reality -- just as the Buddhist doctrines of <I>Nirvana</I> and space as unconditioned things parallel the Kantian theory of "Ideas" and the <a href="antinom.htm">Antinomies</a>. Furthermore, Kant's theory of the Antinomies now can be extended to Set Theory, where it has become evident that an unconditioned whole, like the Universal Set, produces contradictions -- famous paradoxes like Russell's, or the Nelson-Grelling Paradox introduced in the pages of the <I>Abhandlungen der Fries'schen Schule, Neue Folge</I> itself. <P><li><B>The dimension of <I>value</I> in objects.</B> <a href="key.htm">Hume's</a> famous distinction between matters of fact and matters of value has led many people to assume that "value judgments" have no basis in reality, since the reality that we perceive is factual. Hume's distinction, however, would be no surprise to Plato, who believed that value was based, not on the things of experience, but on the transcendent Forms. Kantian theory is that such a transcendent aspect of things is not a <I>separate World</I>, as Plato had thought, but is present in things-in-themselves. The view that <I>all</I> we perceive in phenomenal objects is <I>factual</I>, however, is mistaken. Plato himself esteemed <B><I>beauty</I></B> as the particular form of value that actually can be <I>seen</I> in things. To make this consistent with the rest of his theory, however, he had to say that beautiful objects were only "shadows" of the higher reality, "participating" in the Form of Beauty. Although Kant's own aesthetics were subjectivist (the theory of the <I>Critique of Judgment</I>), his metaphysics could allow for a more literal rendering of Plato's own claim about beauty: Since transcendence is <I>in</I> phenomenal objects, the beauty that we see in things is in fact a perception right <I>through</I> factual reality to Beauty Itself. </ol> <P><a name="system">Kantian metaphysics, with some minor</a> clarifications and modifications, thus accomplishes a great deal, especially in providing a sort of "phase space" for matters of value, although much the same thing had originally been done by Plato. See also "<a href="system.htm">A New Kant-Friesian System of Metaphysics</a>" and "<a href="universl.htm">Meaning and the Problem of Universals, A Kant-Friesian Approach</a>." <p><li><H2>Ethics and Value Theory</H2> <P>Kant's desire to derive the ultimate principle of morality, and really of all value, from the pure form, universality, and rule making function of reason itself was not well conceived, successful, or persuasive. Nevertheless, his project can be sympathetically interpreted and reformed. The Moral Law, as a synthetic <I>a priori</I> proposition, actually cannot be derived from anything, let alone some logician's version of what reason is. Nelson was correct that Socratic Method would be the means to the discovery of such propositions, though, as I have noted, the logic of Socratic Method must be clarified through Popper's insights into falsification. The <a href="moral-1.htm">Moral Law</a>, indeed, may be formulated rather like Kant's own "means and ends" version, though Schopenhauer claimed not to understand what this was supposed to mean. <P>The other problem with Kant's project was its <a href="poly-1b.htm">moralism</a>: The view that morality is ultimately the only form of value, which is implied by the idea that morality is the direct dictation of the form of reason itself. Following Schiller's denial of this, Nelson ultimately developed a complete theory of ethical "Ideals" that were not merely <I>moral</I> ideals. This kind of theory is here labelled the <a href="poly-1.htm">Polynomic Theory of Value</a>, and is elaborated beyond Nelson to specify that there are <a href="domain.htm">six "domains"</a> of value that are axiomatically independent of each other. This allows for a realistic view of aesthetics, as suggested under "Metaphysics" above. <p><li><H2>Political Economy</H2> <P>A conspicuous thing about the lives of both Fries and Nelson was their political activism. In both cases, this was not always to good effect. In the long run, Fries may be said to have been on the "right side" in resistance to Prussian and Austrian Reaction, but this also involved a promotion of German racialist nationalism that ultimately very much became the "wrong side." Nelson, in turn, was forthrightly opposed to the nationalism that would eventually motivate Germans to draw much of Europe down into a living hell of tyranny, war, and mass murder; but he also mistakenly subscribed to socialist principles that helped promote totalitarian regimes and also introduced corrupting and dangerous influences even into the democracies, the consequences of which have still not played out entirely. When this was first written, I was worried about the election and re&euml;lection of <a href="presiden.htm#43">Bill Clinton</a> in the United States in 1992 and 1996, and the return to power of the British Laborites and French Socialists in 1997, and German Socialists in 1998. In the United States, danger loomed with the election and re&euml;lection of <a href="presiden.htm#45">Barack Obama in 2008 and 2012, and then with the catastrophic election of the corrupt and senile <a href="presiden.htm#46">Joe Biden</a> in 2020. Things almost seem better in Britain, France, and Germany, but the economic damage of the Wuhan Virus lockdowns has given states more power and has encouraged the forces hostile to economic growth and even to small business. <P>The Friesian tradition, however, leads to classic and brilliant defenses of capitalism. Popper's understanding of falsification inspired his friend <a href="hayek.htm">F.A. Hayek</a> in his formulation of the principles of Austrian Economics originally developed by Ludwig von Mises. In retrospect, the Austrian theory that the free market serves to co&ouml;rdinate <I>limited and diffused knowledge</I> may be assimilated to a Popperian reformulation of <a href="foundatn.htm">Socratic Method</a>, in that each is a means of dealing with our own ignorance, a self-aware <a href="socrates.htm">Socratic Ignorance</a>. Similarly, Nelson's suspicions of democracy can be set aside on the same principles. The defense of capitalism may also be assimilated to the Polynomic Theory of Value; for capitalism on the Austrian interpretation requires that the <I>values</I> exchanged in the free market be relative and different: Parties A and B exchange goods X and Y because X really is <I>more valuable</I> to B than to A and Y really is <I>more valuable</I> to A than to B. That is why the exchange takes place. Thus, the relativity of non-moral ethical value ("hortative" value here) is distinct from the absolute requirements of moral value ("imperative" value ever since Kant). <P>The Friesian tradition has long been playing catch up with Adam Smith, but fortunately, with F.A. Hayek, it caught up and went ahead. In the <I>Proceedings of the Friesian School, Fourth Series</I>, the tradition may now be fully integrated into the great heritage of Classical Liberalism. As Karl Popper and Julius Kraft moved the focus of the School to Britain, it is appropriate that the English language continuation of the School in this journal should more fully assimilate the <a href="quiz.htm">Liberal</a> content of the English tradition, which is at once so characteristic of it and at the same time so different from the hostility to Liberal principles that marked Germany and German philosophy in the days of both Fries and Nelson (e.g. Hegel and Heidegger) and even still today (when Heidegger has been turned into "deconstruction" and "post-modernism" -- both bywords for trendy leftism, as in the case of Richard Rorty). <p><li><H2>Philosophy of Religion</H2> <P>Fries's view of religion had added an aesthetic dimension to Kant's moralistic "religion within the limits of reason alone." Nelson's associate <a href="otto.htm">Rudolf Otto</a>, however, recognized that religion contained even more than this: The sense of the "sacred" or the "holy" was not just a matter of moral judgment, as Kant had thought, nor even also just a matter of aesthetic judgment, as Fries had added, but was special and <I>sui generis</I> in its own independent <a href="numinos.htm">modality</a>. <a href="system.htm"><img src="images/onto-14.gif" align=right border=0></a>The only argument Otto needed for this was a descriptive and phenomenological one based on historical religions. That God might ask Abraham to sacrifice his son, or that Jesus might take the sins of the world upon himself in the Crucifixion, or that Salvation might be by "faith alone," as separately taught by Luther and <a href="six.htm#japan">Shinran</a>, are all aspects of religion that could not be captured either by morality or by aesthetics. The traditional response of philosophers, ever since Xenophanes and Socrates, was to ignore or dismiss them as immoral or unedifying; but this clearly fails to "save the phenomena." Only Otto, on the basis of Friesian epistemology and metaphysics, could realize their significance. "Salvation" as a religious concept, whether in Christianity, Islam, Hinduism, or Buddhism, is independent of morality and aesthetics. Even in Judaism, "walking in the ways of the Lord," clearly involves obeying regulations for ritual purity and distinctive behaviors that cannot be given either a moral or aesthetic justification. While the <I>bien pensants</I> at the beginning of the 20th Century figured that religion would wither away in the face of scientific enlightenment, this did not happen; and at the beginning of the 21th Century the danger of religious <a href="afghan.htm#fascism">fanaticism</a> feeding large scale wars is greater than it has been since perhaps the <a href="francia.htm#hapsburg-2">Thirty Years War</a>. While this has enabled frank <a href="atheism.htm">atheists</a> (e.g. Christopher Hitchens, Richard Dawkins) to again blame human evils on religion, they are in the awkward position of explaining why their alternative has remained so unpopular (or, for that matter, was associated with ideological <a href="potter.htm#note-2">mass murder</a> in the 20th Century). Instead, people have understood all too well that a world merely of science, without religious transcendence, is a bleak <a href="existent.htm">Existential</a> desert, devoid of meaning. With the addition of Otto and Hayek, the Friesian School hopefully achieves a broad, enlightened, and non-reductionistic approach to all the problems of philosophy and of the human condition. </ul> <p><center><img src="images/key.gif"></center> <P>Return to <a href="./#school">Friesian School</a> on the Home Page<p> Return to <a href="./#critical">The Project of the Friesian School</a> on the Home Page<p> <a href="school.htm">The Sources and Influence of the Kant-Friesian School</a><p> <a href="./ross/#curse">The Curse of the Friesian School</a><p> <a href="history.htm">History of Philosophy</a><p> <a href="./#contents">Home Page Contents</a><p> <H5>Copyright (c) 1997, 1998, 1999, 2000, 2001, 2007, 2017, 2018, 2020, 2021 <a href="./ross/">Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D.</a> All <a href="./#ross">Rights</a> Reserved</H5> </BODY> </HTML>

Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10