CINXE.COM

CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Civil Authority

<!DOCTYPE html> <html lang="en"> <head> <title>CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Civil Authority</title><script src="https://dtyry4ejybx0.cloudfront.net/js/cmp/cleanmediacmp.js?ver=0104" async="true"></script><script defer data-domain="newadvent.org" src="https://plausible.io/js/script.js"></script><link rel="canonical" href="https://www.newadvent.org/cathen/02137c.htm"> <meta name="viewport" content="width=device-width, initial-scale=1"> <meta name="description" content="The moral power of command, supported by physical coercion, which the State exercises over its members"> <meta http-equiv="Content-Type" content="text/html; charset=utf-8"><link rel="alternate" type="application/rss+xml" title="RSS" href="http://feeds.newadvent.org/bestoftheweb?format=xml"><link rel="icon" href="../images/icon1.ico" type="image/x-icon"><link rel="shortcut icon" href="../images/icon1.ico" type="image/x-icon"><meta name="robots" content="noodp"><link type="text/css" rel="stylesheet" href="../utility/screen6.css" media="screen"></head> <body class="cathen" id="02137c.htm"> <!-- spacer-->&nbsp;<br/> <div id="capitalcity"><table summary="Logo" cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0 width="100%"><tr valign="bottom"><td align="left"><a href="../"><img height=36 width=153 border="0" alt="New Advent" src="../images/logo.gif"></a></td><td align="right"> <form id="searchbox_000299817191393086628:ifmbhlr-8x0" action="../utility/search.htm"> <!-- Hidden Inputs --> <input type="hidden" name="safe" value="active"> <input type="hidden" name="cx" value="000299817191393086628:ifmbhlr-8x0"/> <input type="hidden" name="cof" value="FORID:9"/> <!-- Search Box --> <label for="searchQuery" id="searchQueryLabel">Search:</label> <input id="searchQuery" name="q" type="text" size="25" aria-labelledby="searchQueryLabel"/> <!-- Submit Button --> <label for="submitButton" id="submitButtonLabel" class="visually-hidden">Submit Search</label> <input id="submitButton" type="submit" name="sa" value="Search" aria-labelledby="submitButtonLabel"/> </form> <table summary="Spacer" cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0><tr><td height="2"></td></tr></table> <table summary="Tabs" cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0><tr> <td bgcolor="#ffffff"></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_color_on_beige" href="../">&nbsp;Home&nbsp;</a></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_white_on_color" href="../cathen/index.html">&nbsp;Encyclopedia&nbsp;</a></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_color_on_beige" href="../summa/index.html">&nbsp;Summa&nbsp;</a></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_color_on_beige" href="../fathers/index.html">&nbsp;Fathers&nbsp;</a></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_color_on_beige" href="../bible/gen001.htm">&nbsp;Bible&nbsp;</a></td> <td class="tab"><a class="tab_color_on_beige" href="../library/index.html">&nbsp;Library&nbsp;</a></td> </tr></table> </td> </tr></table><table summary="Alphabetical index" width="100%" cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0><tr><td class="bar_white_on_color"> <a href="../cathen/a.htm">&nbsp;A&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/b.htm">&nbsp;B&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/c.htm">&nbsp;C&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/d.htm">&nbsp;D&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/e.htm">&nbsp;E&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/f.htm">&nbsp;F&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/g.htm">&nbsp;G&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/h.htm">&nbsp;H&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/i.htm">&nbsp;I&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/j.htm">&nbsp;J&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/k.htm">&nbsp;K&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/l.htm">&nbsp;L&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/m.htm">&nbsp;M&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/n.htm">&nbsp;N&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/o.htm">&nbsp;O&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/p.htm">&nbsp;P&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/q.htm">&nbsp;Q&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/r.htm">&nbsp;R&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/s.htm">&nbsp;S&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/t.htm">&nbsp;T&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/u.htm">&nbsp;U&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/v.htm">&nbsp;V&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/w.htm">&nbsp;W&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/x.htm">&nbsp;X&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/y.htm">&nbsp;Y&nbsp;</a><a href="../cathen/z.htm">&nbsp;Z&nbsp;</a> </td></tr></table></div> <div id="mobilecity" style="text-align: center; "><a href="../"><img height=24 width=102 border="0" alt="New Advent" src="../images/logo.gif"></a></div> <!--<div class="scrollmenu"> <a href="../utility/search.htm">SEARCH</a> <a href="../cathen/">Encyclopedia</a> <a href="../summa/">Summa</a> <a href="../fathers/">Fathers</a> <a href="../bible/">Bible</a> <a href="../library/">Library</a> </div> <br />--> <div id="mi5"><span class="breadcrumbs"><a href="../">Home</a> > <a href="../cathen">Catholic Encyclopedia</a> > <a href="../cathen/a.htm">A</a> > Civil Authority</span></div> <div id="springfield2"> <div class='catholicadnet-728x90' id='cathen-728x90-top' style='display: flex; height: 100px; align-items: center; justify-content: center; '></div> <h1>Civil Authority</h1> <p><em><a href="https://gumroad.com/l/na2"><strong>Please help support the mission of New Advent</strong> and get the full contents of this website as an instant download. Includes the Catholic Encyclopedia, Church Fathers, Summa, Bible and more &#151; all for only $19.99...</a></em></p> <p>Civil Authority is the moral power of command, supported (when need be) by physical coercion, which the State exercises over its members. We shall consider here the <a href="../cathen/10715a.htm">nature</a>, sources, limits, divisions, origin, and the <a href="../cathen/15073a.htm">true</a> and <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> theories of authority. Authority is as great a necessity to <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">mankind</a> as sobriety, and as natural. By "natural" here is meant, not what accrues to man without any effort of his own (teeth, for example), but what man must secure, even with an effort, because without it he cannot well be man. It is natural to man to live in civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>; and where there is civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, there must be authority. <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">Anarchy</a> is the disruption of <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>. Speaking generally, we may say no man loves isolation, solitude, loneliness, the life of a <a href="../cathen/07280a.htm">hermit</a>; on the other hand, while many dislike the authority under which they live, no man wishes for <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a>. What malcontents aim at is a change of government, to get authority into their own hands and govern those who now govern them. Even the professed anarchist regards <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a> as a temporary expedient, a preparation for his own advent to power. Authority, then, in the abstract, every man loves and cherishes; and rightly so, for it is his nature to live in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, and <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> is kept together by authority. The model of <a href="../cathen/07280a.htm">hermits</a> was St. Simeon Stylites, so called from his living on the top of a style, or pillar. That was his special vocation; he was no ordinary man. But the political <a href="../cathen/12025c.htm">philosopher</a> considers man as man ordinarily and normally is. Two things would strike a stranger from Mars looking down upon this planet: how men on earth <a href="../cathen/09397a.htm">love</a> herding together, and how they <a href="../cathen/09397a.htm">love</a> moving about. Ordinary man can no more afford to be solitary than he can afford to be stationary, though Simeon Stylites was both. Solitary confinement is the severest of punishments, next to death. It is hard to say whether the solitude or the confinement, proves the more irksome. This simple point, that man cannot live alone, must be insisted upon, for all <a href="../cathen/05525a.htm">errors</a> in the theory of authority are rooted in the assumption that man's living in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, and thereby coming to be governed by social authority, is something purely optional and conventional, a fashion which man could very well discard if he would, as he might discard the wearing of green clothes. Men who would make <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> a conventional arrangement, and authority a fashion of the hour, have appealed to the noble savage as the standard of humanity proper, forgetting that the savage is no solitary, but a member of a horde, to separate from which would be death, and to ignore the control of which would be death also. Man must live in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, and, in point of historical fact, men have always lived in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>; every human development is a social progress. It is natural to man to live in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, to submit to authority, and to be governed by that custom of <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> which crystallizes into law.</p> <div class="CMtag_300x250" style="display: flex; height: 300px; align-items: center; justify-content: center; "></div> <p>And as it is natural to the individual, so is it natural also for the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a> to unite with others. Society cannot stop short at the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a>. As the individual is not sell-sufficient, neither is the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a>. The <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a> grows and then multiplies. We have a <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> of <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">families</a>; and that <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> grown great, and controlled as it needs to be controlled by some common authority, passes into a self-sufficient, autonomous <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, otherwise called a State. Hence civil authority is defined as the moral power of command, supported (when need be) by physical coercion, which the State exercises over its constituent members. Civil authority is of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>, not by any revelation or positive institution, but by the mere fact that <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> is the Author of Nature, and Nature imperatively requires civil authority to be set up and obeyed. Nature cannot tolerate intemperance, nor <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a> either. And what Nature absolutely requires, or absolutely refuses as incompatible with her well-being, <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> commands, or <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> forbids. <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> then forbids <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a>; and in forbidding <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a> He enjoins submission to authority. In this sense, <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> is at the back of every State, binding men in <a href="../cathen/04268a.htm">conscience</a> to observe the behests of the State within the sphere of its competence. "Let every <a href="../cathen/14153a.htm">soul</a> be subject to higher powers: for there is no power but from <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>: and those that are, are <a href="../cathen/11279a.htm">ordained</a> of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>. . . . Wherefore be subject of necessity, not only for wrath, but also for <a href="../cathen/04268a.htm">conscience</a> sake. . . . For they are the <a href="../cathen/10326a.htm">ministers</a> of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>, . ." (<a href="../bible/rom013.htm#1">Romans 13:1, 5-6</a>).</p> <p>Obedience, being a practical thing and not a speculation, cannot abstract from the concrete facts of the case; it is paid to the powers that be, to the authority actually in possession. Obedience is as disobedience; men are never disobedient except to the government of the day. But there are limits to civil obedience, and to the competence of civil authority. As domestic obedience is not to be carried to the extent of rebellion against the civil government, so neither is the State to be obeyed as against <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>. It is not within the competence of the State to command anything and everything. The State cannot command what <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> could not command, for instance, <a href="../cathen/07636a.htm">idolatry</a>. The authority of the State is absolute, that is to say, full and complete in its own sphere, and subordinate to no other authority within that sphere. But the authority of the State is not arbitrary; it is not available for the carrying out of every whim and caprice. Arbitrary government is irrational government; now no government is licensed to set reason aside. The government of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> Himself is not arbitrary; as <a href="../cathen/14663b.htm">St. Thomas</a> says: "<a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> is not offended by us except at what we do against our own good" (Contra Gentiles, III, 122). The arbitrary use of authority is called tyranny. Such is the tyranny of an absolute monarch, of a council, of a class, or of a majority. The liberty of the subject is based on the <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> that the State is not <a href="../cathen/11251c.htm">omnipotent</a>. Legally <a href="../cathen/11251c.htm">omnipotent</a> every State must be, but not morally. A legal enactment may be immoral, and then it cannot in <a href="../cathen/04268a.htm">conscience</a> be obeyed; or it may be ultra vires, beyond the competence of the authority that enacts it, in which case compliance with the <a href="../cathen/09053a.htm">law</a> is not a matter of obedience, but of <a href="../cathen/12517b.htm">prudence</a>. In either case the <a href="../cathen/09053a.htm">law</a> is tyrannical, and "a tyrannical law, not being according to reason, is not, absolutely speaking, a law, but rather a perversion of law" (St. Thomas, <a href="../summa/2092.htm#article1">Summa Theol., I-II.92.1 ad 4</a>). Man is not all citizen. He is a member, a part of the State, and something else besides. "Man is not subservient to the civil community to the extent of his whole self, all that he is and all that he has" (St. Thomas, <a href="../summa/2021.htm#article4">Summa Theol., I-II.21.4 ad 3</a>). To say nothing of his eternal interests in his relations with his Maker, man has even in this life his domestic interests in the bosom of his <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a>, his <a href="../cathen/08066a.htm">intellectual</a> and artistic interests, none of which can be called political interests. Social and political life is not the whole of <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">human</a> <a href="../cathen/09238c.htm">life</a>. Man is not the servant of the State in his every action. The State, the majority, or the despot, may demand of the individual more than he is bound to give. Were human <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> a conventional arrangement, were man, being perfectly well off in isolation from his fellows, to agree by way of freak to live in community with them, then we could assign no antecedent limits to civil authority. Civil authority would be simply what was bargained for and prescribed in the arbitrary compact which made civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>. As it is, civil authority is a natural means to a natural end and is checked by that end, in accordance with the <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotelean</a> principle that "the end in view sets limits to the means" (Aristotle, Politics, I, 9). The immediate end of civil authority is well set forth by Francisco Su&aacute;rez (De legibus, LII, xi, 7) as "the natural <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happiness</a> of the perfect, or self-sufficient, human community, and the <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happiness</a> of <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a> as they are members of such a community, that they may live therein peaceably and justly, with a sufficiency of goods for the preservation and comfort of their bodily life, and with so much moral rectitude as is <a href="../cathen/10733a.htm">necessary</a> for this external peace and <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happiness</a>". Happiness is an attribute of <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a>. Individuals are not made <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happy</a> by authority, but authority secures to them that tranquillity, that free hand for helping themselves, that restful enjoyment of their own just winnings, which is one of the conditions of <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happiness</a>. Nor does authority make men virtuous, except according to that rough-hewn, outline virtue, which is called "social virtue", and consists mainly of <a href="../cathen/08571c.htm">justice</a>. When the ancients spoke of "virtue" being the concern of the State, they meant <a href="../cathen/08571c.htm">justice</a> and efficiency. Neither the virtue nor the <a href="../cathen/07131b.htm">happiness</a> of <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a> is cared for by the State except "as they are members of the civil community". In this respect, civil differs from domestic, or paternal, authority. The father cares for the members of his household one by one, singly and individually. The State cares for its members collectively, and for the individual only in his collective aspect. Hence it follows that the power of life and death is inherent in the State, not in the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a>. A man is hanged for the common good of the rest, never for his own good.</p> <div class="CMtag_300x250" style="display: flex; height: 300px; align-items: center; justify-content: center; "></div> <p>This, then, is one measure of authority, the end which the State has in view. Another is the stage of development at which any given particular State has arrived. For there is not one measure of authority common to all States. As the State develops, it grows in unity, and greater unity means an ampler measure of central authority. There is far more authority in the <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a> of today than in the <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a> of the <a href="../cathen/07241d.htm">Heptarchy</a>. There was more authority in an Anglo-Saxon kingdom than in a horde of savages. In early civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">societies</a> there is no legislative authority, and no law, but only immemorial custom. There is little judicial authority, but injured men, or their <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">families</a> after their death, right their own wrongs, <a href="../cathen/07441a.htm">murder</a> is restrained, not by judge, jury, and executioner, but by blood-feud. On the other hand, in highly civilized <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">societies</a>, especially those of a democratic character, the will of the people continually thrusts new functions upon government, such as <a href="../cathen/05295b.htm">education</a>, the care of public health, the carrying of letters, the sending of telegrams. The recognition of this fact has been called "the principle of <a href="../cathen/15506a.htm">voluntary</a> control". By it civil authority may be enlarged beyond its natural and essential limits. Like other principles, "the principle of <a href="../cathen/15506a.htm">voluntary</a> control" may be pushed too far. Pushed to the limit, it would involve Socialism. Authority, though varying in amount, is as universal as man is everywhere. Man cannot live except under authority, as he cannot live out of civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>. It is by no convention, compact, or contract, that authority takes hold of him. It is a necessity of his nature. But while civil authority, or government, is natural and universal, the distribution of authority, otherwise called the form of government, or the constitution of the State, is a human convention, varying in various countries, and in the same country at different periods of its history. It is scarcely too much to say that there are as many various distributions of civil authority, or various forms of government, as there are varieties of vertebrate animals. They are classified as monarchies, aristocracies, democracies; but no two monarchies are quite alike, nor two democracies. Thus a democracy may be direct, as in ancient Athens, or representative, as in the <a href="../cathen/15156a.htm">United States</a>. The monarchy of Edward VII is different from that of George III.</p> <p>The one point fixed by nature, and by <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>, is that there must be authority everywhere, and that the authority existent for the time being, under such and such a form, be under that form obeyed; for since there is no actual authority in the country except under that form, to refuse to obey that is to refuse authority simply, and to revert to <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a>, which is against nature: just as a man having nothing but bread and cheese to eat, and refusing to eat his bread and cheese, under pretence that he much prefers mutton, condemns himself to starvation, which again is unnatural. But we must beware of saying of any particular form of authority, monarchy for example, or democracy either, what is <a href="../cathen/15073a.htm">true</a> only of authority in the abstract, namely, that all nations are bound to live under it, and that never under any pretence can it be subverted. A country, once monarchical, is not <a href="../cathen/05551b.htm">eternally</a> bound to monarchy; and circumstances are conceivable under which a republic might pass into monarchy, as <a href="../cathen/13164a.htm">Rome</a> did under <a href="../cathen/02107a.htm">Augustus</a>, much to its advantage. Authority rules by Divine right under whatsoever form it is established. No one form of government is more sacred and inviolate than another. Change of <a href="../cathen/11726a.htm">persons</a> holding office is usually provided in the constitution, sometimes by rotation, sometimes by vote of the legislative assembly. No monarchical constitution provides for the change of the <a href="../cathen/11726a.htm">person</a> of the monarch otherwise than by death or resignation. Change of the form of government can be effected constitutionally, but, as history shows, as often as not, it is brought about unconstitutionally. When the change is complete, the new government rules by right of accomplished fact. There must be authority in the country, and theirs is the only authority available.</p> <h2>Divisions</h2> <p>The progress of civilization subdivides authority into legislative, judicial, and executive, and the latter again into civil and military. The king, or president, is chief of the executive. Authority again is subdivided into imperial and local, the latter emanating from the former and subordinate to it.</p> <h2>Origin</h2> <p>The question of the origin of authority seems first to have been raised by the Roman lawyers. In their hands it assumed the concrete form of the origin of the imperial power. This power they argued to reside primarily in the Roman people; the people, however, did not exercise nor retain it, but transferred it by some implicit <em>lex regia,</em> or king-making ordinance, as a matter of course wholly, and irrevocably to each successive emperor at his accession. With the advent of <a href="../cathen/03712a.htm">Christianity</a>, <a href="../cathen/11567b.htm">St. Paul's</a> <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> came into prominence, that authority is of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>; yet in no clear way was it made out how it came of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> until <a href="../cathen/14663b.htm">St. Thomas Aquinas</a> showed that it was of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> inasmuch as it was an essential of the <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">human</a> <a href="../cathen/10715a.htm">nature</a> which <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> has created, according to the <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> of <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotle</a> above exposed. Before <a href="../cathen/14663b.htm">St. Thomas</a> arose, some <a href="../cathen/04049b.htm">churchmen</a> had shown a disposition to cry down the civil power. They could not deny that it was of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>, but they regarded it as one of the consequences of the <a href="../cathen/14004b.htm">sin</a> of Adam, and argued that, but for the Fall, man would have lived free from coercive <a href="../cathen/08567a.htm">jurisdiction</a>. They rehearsed the legend of Romulus, and the asylum that he opened for robbers. States, they said, usually have their origin in rapine and <a href="../cathen/08010c.htm">injustice</a>. Others invested the <a href="../cathen/12260a.htm">pope</a> with the plenitude of secular as well as spiritual authority, by the gift of <a href="../cathen/08374c.htm">Christ</a>, and argued that kings reigned only as his vicegerents, even in civil matters. The <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristoteleanism</a> of St. Thomas was opposed to all this. On the other hand, the imperial and royal party made a <a href="../cathen/12260a.htm">pope</a> of the king or emperor; the civil ruler was as much an institution of Christ as the <a href="../cathen/12260a.htm">pope</a> himself, and, like the <a href="../cathen/12260a.htm">pope</a>, enjoyed a God-given authority, no portion of which could validly be taken from him. This is the <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> of "the divine right of kings". According to it, in its rigour, in a State once monarchical, monarchy is forever the only lawful government, and all authority is vested in the monarch, to be communicated by him, to such as he may select for the time being to share his power. This "divine right of kings" (very different from the <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> that all authority, whether of king or of republic, is from <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>), has never been sanctioned by the <a href="../cathen/03449a.htm">Catholic</a> <a href="../cathen/03744a.htm">Church</a>. At the <a href="../cathen/12700b.htm">Reformation</a> it assumed a form exceedingly hostile to <a href="../cathen/03449a.htm">Catholicism</a>, monarchs like <a href="../cathen/07222a.htm">Henry VIII</a>, and James I, of <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a>, claiming the fullness of spiritual as well as of civil authority, and this in such inalienable possession that no jot or tittle of prerogative could ever pass away from the Crown. Against these monstrous pretensions were fought the battles of Marston Moor and Naseby.</p> <p>Against the same pretensions a more pacific <a href="../cathen/15546c.htm">warfare</a> was waged by <a href="../cathen/14319a.htm">Francisco Su&aacute;rez, S.J.</a> Su&aacute;rez argued against James I that spiritual authority is not vested in the Crown, and that even civil authority is not the immediate <a href="../cathen/06553a.htm">gift of God</a> to the king, but is given by <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> to the people collectively, and by them bestowed on the monarch, according to the theory of the Roman lawyers above mentioned, and according to <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotle</a> and <a href="../cathen/14663b.htm">St. Thomas</a>. Authority, he asserted, is an attribute of a multitude assembled to form a State. By their nature they must form a State, and a State must have authority. Authority, therefore, is natural to <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">mankind</a> collectively; and whatever is natural, and rational, and indispensable for human progress, is an ordinance of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>. Authority must be, and <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> will have it to be; but there is no such natural necessity of authority being all centred in one <a href="../cathen/11726a.htm">person</a>. Authority is a Divine institution, but kings are a human invention. The saying is a platitude in our time; three centuries ago, when Francisco Su&aacute;rez wrote, it was a bold and startling pronouncement. Francisco Su&aacute;rez saved his loyalty by the concession that the people having bestowed the supreme power on His Majesty's ancestors ages ago, their posterity could not now resume it, but it must descend, like an heirloom, from the king to the king's son for all time. This concession was not everywhere borne in mind by posterity. Indeed it would appear a restriction on the development of a State for the distribution of authority to be thus fixed forever. In <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a> at any rate the restriction has been broken through, and the king is not what he was in Stuart times, nor the Parliament either.</p> <h2>Theories</h2> <div class="CMtag_300x250" style="display: flex; height: 300px; align-items: center; justify-content: center; "></div> <p>There have been two great outbreaks against excess of royal prerogative; one in <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a>, in the middle of the seventeenth century; another in <a href="../cathen/06166a.htm">France</a>, at the end of the eighteenth. Each of these two periods was marked by the appearance of a great political writer, Thomas Hobbes in <a href="../cathen/05445a.htm">England</a>, Jean Jacques Rousseau in <a href="../cathen/06166a.htm">France</a>. Hobbes was a <a href="../cathen/12025c.htm">philosopher</a>, Rousseau a rhetorician. Whoever knows Hobbes well can have little to learn from Rousseau. Hobbes is rigidly <a href="../cathen/09324a.htm">logical</a>; such inconsistencies as appear in him come from a certain timidity in speaking out, and a <a href="../cathen/07543b.htm">humility</a> that approaches nigh to <a href="../cathen/07610a.htm">hypocrisy</a>. Rousseau always speaks boldly, makes no pretence to <a href="../cathen/11330a.htm">orthodoxy</a>, and frequently contradicts himself. His brilliant style won him the ear of <a href="../cathen/05607b.htm">Europe</a>; he popularized Hobbes. To the <a href="../cathen/12025c.htm">philosopher</a>, Rousseau is contemptible, but Hobbes is an antagonist worthy of any man's steel. The best that can be said of Rousseau in <a href="../cathen/12025c.htm">philosophy</a> is that he drew out of Hobbes's principles conclusions which Hobbes was afraid to formulate. Hobbes made of the king a despot; Rousseau showed that, on Hobbesian principles, a king is no better than the people's bailiff, unless indeed, by military force or otherwise, he can prevent the people from assembling and decreeing his deposition.</p> <p>Hobbes starts, and Rousseau after him, by contradicting <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotle</a>. According to <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotle</a>, man is "by nature a State-making animal"; the individual man, if he is to thrive at all, develops into the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a> man, and the <a href="../cathen/05782a.htm">family</a> man into the citizen; and wherever there is a city, or a nation, there must be self-government, or, in other words, civil authority, whether vested in one or in many. Authority is the very breath of man's nostrils, as he is a progressive being. Isolation and <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a> are fatal to human progress. Effort, without which man cannot thrive, though it be an effort, and not an initial endowment passively received, <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotle</a> calls "natural". The State-making effort is "natural" to man; so is authority "natural", and, as such, of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>, adds <a href="../cathen/14663b.htm">Thomas Aquinas</a>. But Hobbes took "natural" in quite another sense. That he held to be "natural" which man is, antecedently to all effort and arrangement on his part to make himself better. Further, his philosophy was tinged with the <a href="../cathen/03198a.htm">Calvinism</a> of his day, and he took it that man is of himself "desperately wicked". What was natural, then, was bad, bad on the whole. Reason being an original endowment of man, Hobbes allowed reason to be natural. He allowed also, with <a href="../cathen/12159a.htm">Plato</a>, that wickedness is irrational, by which concession Hobbism is marked off from a celebrated theory stated at the beginning of the second book of <a href="../cathen/12159a.htm">Plato's</a> Republic, to which theory in other respects it bears a strong resemblance; the theory being that right by nature is the interest of the stronger, and only by convention becomes the interest of the State.</p> <p>This allowing of wickedness to be against reason is a weak point in the <a href="../cathen/09324a.htm">logic</a> of Hobbes. But Hobbes would have it that reason is by nature utterly unable to contend with wickedness, that it is overborne by, and made subservient to, passion, and so is degraded into cunning, man becoming more wicked by his possession of reason. Of himself, in his "state of <a href="../cathen/10715a.htm">nature</a>", Hobbesian man is a savage, solitary, sensual, and selfish. When two <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">human beings</a> meet, the natural impulse of each is to lord it over the other. By force, if he is strong, by stratagem, if he is weak, every man seeks to kill or enslave every other man that he meets. Man's life in this state of nature, says Hobbes, is "nasty, brutish, and short." So it would be, in an English fen, and in most other places. But Rousseau's <a href="../cathen/07672a.htm">imagination</a> carried him to the Pacific Isles; he became enamoured of "the noble savage". He fell in with Hobbes's notion of the "natural", as being what man is and has antecedently to all human effort. But the "citizen of <a href="../cathen/09040a.htm">Geneva</a>", as he called himself, was curiously free from <a href="../cathen/03198a.htm">Calvinistic</a> bias, and believed enthusiastically in the primitive, unmade, natural <a href="../cathen/06636b.htm">goodness</a> of man. In Hobbes's view, though not in Rousseau's, man had every reason for getting out of his "nasty" state of nature. This was done by a pact, or convention, of every man with all the rest of <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">mankind</a>, to give up solitude with its charms, its independence, and its liberty of preying upon neighbours, and to live in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, the social body thus formed having all the <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a> of the <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a> contributing to form it. This compact of man with man to quit solitude and live in <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>, to abandon nature and submit to convention, was called by Rousseau, "The Social Contract". The body formed by it, commonly called the State, Hobbes termed "The Leviathan", upon the text of <a href="../bible/job041.htm#vrs24">Job 41:24</a>, "there is no power upon earth that can be compared with him. . . ."</p> <p>To Hobbes and to Rousseau the State is <a href="../cathen/11251c.htm">omnipotent</a>, containing in its one self absolutely all the <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a> of the citizens who compose it. The wielder of this tremendous power is the General Will, measured against which the will of the individual citizen is not only powerless, but absolutely non-existent. The individual gave up his will when he made the Social Contract. "No rights against the State", is a fundamental principle with Hobbes and Rousseau. To live in the State at all means compliance with every <a href="../cathen/04670a.htm">decree</a> of the General Will. But there is a difficulty in locating this General Will. Hobbes, with laudable perspicacity, seeing that tyranny is better wielded by one man than by a multitude, contemplates the multitude resigning all their power into the hands of a Single Person, and denying themselves the right of meeting without his calling them together; so that, by the simple expedient of never calling them together, the Single Person may incapacitate the people from ever resuming the power which is only theirs when they are all assembled. The General Will in that case is the will of the Single Person. Hobbes's location of the General Will is not lacking in clearness. But Rousseau would have the sovereign authority to be the inalienable right of the multitude &#151; hence called the "Sovereign People". They may, if they will, employ a king, or even an emperor; but his majesty, in Rousseau's phrase, is "Prince" not "Sovereign", and at stated times, without his calling them together, the Sovereign People must meet and decide, first, whether they will continue to support a throne at all; secondly, whether the throne shall further be filled by the present occupant. Rousseau's location is also clear, so long as it is understood that the General Will is simply the will of the numerical majority of the Sovereign People. Such a General Will is ascertained by the simple process of counting heads. If in a State of 20,000 citizens, 15,000 vote aye, aye is the General Will, not the will of the majority only, but of the whole 20,000 together; for though 5,000 <a href="../cathen/11726a.htm">persons</a> detest the proposal, such detestation lies only in the individual will, sometimes called the "casual will", and the individual will has ceased to exist by the Compact. Personally they detest the measure, but with their "Real Will" they approve it. Thus, as Rousseau says, they remain as free as the wild man in the woods, obey none but themselves, and follow their own will everywhere.</p> <p>But a canker-worm lies at the root of this, as of all ultra-democratic doctrines. All originate in a manifestly <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> supposition, that one man is as good as another. In any sane polity, the predominant Intelligence must guide the counsels of the State, not the predominant Will, which may be no better than caprice. But intelligence is not necessarily attached to majorities. Rousseau himself falters in presence of this awkward <a href="../cathen/15073a.htm">truth</a>, and re-states the General Will, as the will which the people have of good in general, albeit in a particular case they are mistaken in what they take to be good. Thus they will one thing, and vote for another. The Real Will in this case is not to be gathered from the actual vote of the majority. The Real Will is of that which the majority would have voted for, had they known better. Rousseau's theory contemplates "a people of gods", so he assures us. Such a people would scarce require any government. The ideal, sylvan creatures whom his <a href="../cathen/07672a.htm">imagination</a> brings together to form the Social Contract, if not all very intelligent, may be supposed to be all good listeners to intelligent teaching, and thus Intelligence will govern the majority, and the vote of the majority will be an ideally Real Will. Government is an easy matter on such optimistic presuppositions. The eye, however, glances back upon Hobbes's ruffian primeval, "brutish and nasty". Hobbes's view of <a href="../cathen/09580c.htm">human</a> <a href="../cathen/10715a.htm">nature</a> must check that of Rousseau. Both views are extreme, and the <a href="../cathen/15073a.htm">truth</a> lies between them. The democratic rule of a numerical majority is not of universal application. One has to consider the character of the people, and peoples vary. If in one age or place the people approximate to the character of "a people of gods", or <a href="../cathen/01476d.htm">angels</a>, in another country or another time they may be more like <a href="../cathen/04764a.htm">devils</a>. "Force, devoid of counsel, of its own bulk comes to a crash", says Horace (Odes, III, 4). That is the danger of the General Will.</p> <p>Rousseau, with Hobbes to guide him, starts from a <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> supposition, that the natural state of man is savage solitude, not civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>; he proceeds through the <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> medium of the "Social Contract", <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> because <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> is not a thing of convention; <a href="../cathen/05781a.htm">false</a> again, because out of all keeping with the evidence of history; and he is apt to end in the tyranny of a brute majority, trampling upon the <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a> and consciences of <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a>; or again in <a href="../cathen/01452a.htm">anarchy</a>, his disciples putting too literal a construction upon the promise that henceforth no man shall obey any other than himself.</p> <p>The doctrines of Rousseau have not escaped the censure of the <a href="../cathen/03744a.htm">Church</a>. Rousseau may be recognized in the following propositions, condemned in the Syllabus of <a href="../cathen/12134b.htm">Pius IX</a>: "The State is the source and origin of all <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a>, and its <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a> are unlimited" (n. 39); "Authority is nothing else than numbers, and a sum of material forces" (n. 60): "It is allowable to refuse obedience to lawful princes, and even to rebel against them" (n. 63). <a href="../cathen/09169a.htm">Leo XIII</a>, not content with condemning, teaches positive <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> against Rousseau, to wit: the <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotelean</a> and <a href="../cathen/14698b.htm">Thomist</a> <a href="../cathen/05075b.htm">doctrine</a> already stated. Thus the <a href="../cathen/05413a.htm">Encyclical</a> "Immortale Dei", of November, 1885:</p> <blockquote><p>Man's natural <a href="../cathen/08050b.htm">instinct</a> moves him to live in civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>; for he can not, if dwelling apart, provide himself with the <a href="../cathen/10733a.htm">necessary</a> requirements of life, nor procure the means of developing his faculties. Hence it is Divinely <a href="../cathen/11279a.htm">ordained</a> that he should be born into the <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> and company of men, as well domestic as civil. Only civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> can ensure perfect self-sufficiency of life [an <a href="../cathen/01713a.htm">Aristotelean</a> term]. But since no <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> can hold together unless there be some one over all, impelling <a href="../cathen/07762a.htm">individuals</a> efficaciously and harmoniously to one common purpose, a ruling authority becomes a necessity for every civil commonwealth of men; and this authority, no less than <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a> itself, is natural, and therefore has <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a> for its author. Hence it follows that public power of itself cannot be otherwise than of <a href="../cathen/06608a.htm">God</a>.</p></blockquote> <p>In the theory of Hobbes and Rousseau, Authority is the outcome of contract, not between people and prince, but of every man with every other man to relinquish solitude and its <a href="../cathen/13055c.htm">rights</a>, and live in civil <a href="../cathen/14074a.htm">society</a>. Rousseau is instant in pronouncing that between people and prince there can be no contract, but the prince is a tenant at will, who may be turned out of doors, with or without reason, any day that the Sovereign People assemble to vote upon him. But there is another theory of contract, centuries older than Hobbes, a theory greatly cherished by Locke and the English Whigs, who found in it the justification of the expulsion of James II in 1688. In this theory, the contract is said to lie between the people and their ruler; the ruler is to be obeyed so long as he fulfils certain conditions, known as "the constitution". If he violates the constitution, he forfeits his authority and the people may cast him out. Thus ruler and subject are two "high contracting parties". The ruler has no superiority of status, but of contract only. On this it is to be observed, first, that such a contract lies not in the nature of things, and therefore is not to be taken for granted; but evidence in each particular case should be forthcoming of the contract having been made on those terms as a fact of history. Secondly, this asserted contract labours under the inconvenience that Job declared of old: ". . . in judgment. There is none that may be able to reprove both, and to put his hand between both" (<a href="../bible/job009.htm#vrs32">Job 9:32, 33</a>). The contract cannot be enforced at law, for lack of a judge; in case of dispute, each party pronounces in his own favour, and they are like to fight it out. The result is civil <a href="../cathen/15546c.htm">war</a>, as between Charles I and his Parliament. But really ruler and subjects are not two "high contracting parties", as two nations are. The theory is prejudicial to the unity of the State, and countenances revolution. The theory was brought up to meet that delicate inquiry, "What is to be done when Government abuses its authority?" On which see "Moral Philosophy" (Stonyhurst Series), 338-343.</p> <div class='catholicadnet-728x90' id='cathen-728x90-bottom' style='display: flex; height: 100px; align-items: center; justify-content: center; '></div> <div class="cenotes"><h2>Sources</h2><p class="cenotes">NEWMAN, <em>Aristotle, Politics,</em> (Clarendon Press, Oxford; there is a translation also by Weldon) I; ST. THOMAS, De <em>Regimine Principum,</em> I; LEO XIII, <em>Encyclicals:</em> Latin, five volumes (Tournai); English, <em>The Pope and the People, Select Letters on Social Questions</em> (New York); SUAREZ, <em>Defensio Fidei,</em> III, i, ii, iii; R. W. and A. T. CARLYLE, <em>Medieval Political Theory in the West</em> (London); GIERKE, <em>Political Theories of the Middle Age,</em> tr. by Maitland (Cambridge); RICKABY, <em>Political and Moral Essays, The Origin and Extent of Civil Authority;</em> HOBBES, <em>Leviathan</em> (Cambridge University Press); ROUSSEAU, <em>Le contrat social</em> (London); LOCKE, <em>Of Civil Government;</em> GREEN, <em>Principles of Political Obligation</em> (London and New York); BOSANQUET, <em>Philosophical Theory of the State</em> (London and New York).</p></div> <div class="pub"><h2>About this page</h2><p id="apa"><strong>APA citation.</strong> <span id="apaauthor">Rickaby, J.</span> <span id="apayear">(1907).</span> <span id="apaarticle">Civil Authority.</span> In <span id="apawork">The Catholic Encyclopedia.</span> <span id="apapublisher">New York: Robert Appleton Company.</span> <span id="apaurl">http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/02137c.htm</span></p><p id="mla"><strong>MLA citation.</strong> <span id="mlaauthor">Rickaby, Joseph.</span> <span id="mlaarticle">"Civil Authority."</span> <span id="mlawork">The Catholic Encyclopedia.</span> <span id="mlavolume">Vol. 2.</span> <span id="mlapublisher">New York: Robert Appleton Company,</span> <span id="mlayear">1907.</span> <span id="mlaurl">&lt;http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/02137c.htm&gt;.</span></p><p id="transcription"><strong>Transcription.</strong> <span id="transcriber">This article was transcribed for New Advent by Douglas J. Potter.</span> <span id="dedication">Dedicated to the Sacred Heart of Jesus Christ.</span></p><p id="approbation"><strong>Ecclesiastical approbation.</strong> <span id="nihil"><em>Nihil Obstat.</em> 1907. Remy Lafort, S.T.D., Censor.</span> <span id="imprimatur"><em>Imprimatur.</em> +John M. Farley, Archbishop of New York.</span></p><p id="contactus"><strong>Contact information.</strong> The editor of New Advent is Kevin Knight. My email address is webmaster <em>at</em> newadvent.org. Regrettably, I can't reply to every letter, but I greatly appreciate your feedback &mdash; especially notifications about typographical errors and inappropriate ads.</p></div> </div> <div id="ogdenville"><table summary="Bottom bar" width="100%" cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0><tr><td class="bar_white_on_color"><center><strong>Copyright &#169; 2023 by <a href="../utility/contactus.htm">New Advent LLC</a>. Dedicated to the Immaculate Heart of Mary.</strong></center></td></tr></table><p align="center"><a href="../utility/contactus.htm">CONTACT US</a> | <a href="https://cleanmedia.net/p/?psid=491-308-20180429T2217479770">ADVERTISE WITH NEW ADVENT</a></p></div><!-- Sticky Footer --> <ins class="CANBMDDisplayAD" data-bmd-ad-unit="30849120210203T1734389107AB67D35C03D4A318731A4F337F60B3E" style="display:block"></ins> <script src="https://secureaddisplay.com/au/bmd/"></script> <!-- /Sticky Footer --> <!-- Hide Dynamic Ads --><ins class="CMAdExcludeArticles"></ins><!-- /Hide Dynamic Ads--> </body> </html>

Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10